In a numerous writings for this blog, I’ve distinguished
between moral and aesthetic standards, and referred to Nietzsche’s argument
that slave morality becomes obsolete with the embarrassment of theism by modern
science and that this morality needs to be replaced by a new, aesthetic
conception of the ideal life. But what is the aesthetic perspective and
how is it superior to a moral one?
Morality and the Naturalistic Fallacy
Instead of following Nietzsche’s atheistic reason for
abandoning what we think of as morality, I’d like to give a different one. The
problem I have in mind is that morality comes to suffer inexorably in
comparison with scientific knowledge. Here’s how this has come about. In the
first place, morality in the sense of rules for what people ought to do or to
avoid doing, arose in a social context, as people found themselves
living in larger and larger groups (as hunting and farming methods were
improved, and so on). Resolving conflicts by violence, prompted by each
individual who deems himself wronged, would defeat the point of living in
society as opposed to the wild, which is precisely to escape what Hobbes called
the “war of all against all” in which each creature’s life is “solitary, poor, nasty,
brutish, and short.” And so members of society stipulate certain modes of
conduct to govern group behaviour. Note, for example, that the Ten Commandments
presuppose a set of social circumstances: what’s forbidden is the killing of
another, the stealing of another’s possessions, the worship of other gods, and
what’s prescribed is the honouring of your parents and the performance of the
religious rituals that bind the society together (the Sabbath, for the ancient
Jews). In this respect, morality and religion functioned together, as ways of
maintaining social cohesion.
As cognitive scientists such as Jonathan Haidt point out, reason
evolved as a way of measuring status in a social hierarchy, of persuading
others in a Machiavellian, egocentric fashion, as opposed to being a matter of
impartial, objective logic or science for discovering the absolute Truth. Just
as religions were terribly biased in favour of each self-interested tribe,
reason was biased in favour of each individual who must balance the tribe’s
interests with his or her own. This state of affairs was eventually unsettled
by human curiosity, which led to the discovery of cognitive methods that
undermined rather than upheld social institutions such as the Catholic Church.
With the ascent of modern science, European rationalists elevated pure Reason
as a precondition of social progress, which is to say that these rationalists
duly ridiculed social conventions and overturned traditions. Modern
rationalists learned how nature actually works and developed technological
means of applying that knowledge, which created modern civilization, typically
held, according to the scientistic fallacy, to be an unqualified improvement on
primitive, benighted ways of life.
Shortly after these developments, hyper-rationalists
(empiricists, positivists, skeptics) took modern science to be the standard for
all beliefs, which means that, as David Hume said, nonscientific writings
should figuratively if not actually be set to the flames, including
metaphysical and theological texts. With progress in view--which is to say
liberalism in the classic sense, relative to which current “centrist”
liberalism is a cover for postmodern nihilism and a pragmatic ideology for enforcing
the oligarchs' control of the mob--rationalists thus became aware of the startling
paradox that while the science-centered worship of Reason generates social
progress at one level by enabling higher degrees of happiness, with greater
control of natural processes, this progressive society threatens to destroy
itself.
For along with pseudoscience, superstition, and theological
dogma, morality appears to be a set of beliefs not acquired by the approved
scientific methods, which is to say roughly, by observation or by mathematical
logic, as Hume put it. As Hume pointed out, moral statements about how we ought
to act don’t follow rationally from scientific statements about what the
natural facts are or from analyses of concepts or definitions. Just because
humans actually want to live together instead of alone in the wild, for
example, doesn’t mean we should live peacefully, respecting our
neighbours. All that follows is the calculation that living peacefully is a
more or less effective means of holding society together, and thus a means of satisfying
our desire to preserve society. But the moral force is lost in this pragmatic
translation of a moral imperative. And so rationalism tends to reduce morality
to pragmatism, which applies technoscientific standards of knowledge-driven
human empowerment, to the social sphere. Likewise, just because we actually
stipulate that stealing is wrong and assign a linguistic label to that concept,
doesn’t mean the stipulation is morally right; after all, evil people can
devise a concept for their antisocial purposes and if they’re sufficiently
persuasive or powerful, as in a dictatorship, the stipulation can become
conventional (popular). Might doesn’t make right, nor does popularity.
This is the essence of the naturalistic fallacy,
which was discovered due to the hyper-rationalist’s contrast of modern
scientific beliefs (i.e. of certain mental representations held to be true or false)
with any other kind. Scientific statements are justified by induction,
deduction, appeal to the best explanation, or some other rational method,
whereas moral commandments, needed to maintain social order, are unscientific
and thus as suspicious as any anti-progressive dogma. Arguably, the current postmodern period exhibits the social disharmony and fragmentation that result from greater
awareness of how the liberal’s scientistic notion of progress ironically
threatens to implode so-called advanced societies. Modern noble lies and
science-centered myths no longer enchant; on the contrary, they terrify when
their radical implications are appreciated. As Nietzsche showed,
rationalism destroys theism and morality, which have always been needed to
pacify clever, power-seeking animals like us. Rationalists such as postmodern liberals attempt to compensate by combining their faith in Reason with
oligarchy-subservient consumerism, as though Nietzsche and Lovecraft had not
already shown that hyper-rationalism, the consistent application of reason in
all walks of life, renders a person insane, not to mention unhappy, and as
though the cliché hadn’t already been disseminated that money can’t buy
happiness.
To be sure, modernists proposed other secular defenses of
morality besides pragmatism, such as Kant’s duty-based approach and Bentham’s
utilitarianism. In each case, the name of the game is Scientism and the
game is to provide a pseudoscientific justification of moral judgments, as
though any normative statement follows from the fact that our cognitive
faculties work by generalizing (Kant) or from the pretense of quantifying and
calculating moral values such as happiness (Bentham). Because of the
naturalistic fallacy, these secular theories obfuscate or take as self-evident
some initial moral ideal, whether it be duty or happiness, since rational
argument alone can’t justify such an ideal. As for Aristotle’s virtue ethics,
his theory relies on the quasi-teleological notion of biological function,
which makes his theory comparable to theistic divine command theory. In either
of the latter cases, we have anti-naturalistic anthropocentrism, a projection of the human
notion of purpose onto the whole of nature.
So much for traditional morality. Note, though, that the
problem stems from morality’s social aspect. The point of moral judgments was
to regulate society by offering incentives to compromise. Instead of preying on
each other or acting as vigilantes, we should strive to be good, to be in the
moral right, even if that means we must sacrifice for the group’s greater
well-being. This social function invites reason to replace violence as the mode
of resolving conflicts. Rationalists become radicalized with the Scientific
Revolution, which leads to the discovery of the naturalistic fallacy, which in
turn delegitimizes morality.
The Aesthetic Perspective
Aesthetics, however, lacks this social function and thus
needn’t collapse under its weight as does morality. Whereas moral rules are
about how to behave in a group, aesthetic judgments are individual reactions to
certain qualities. Take, first, the aesthetic distinction between beauty and ugliness. As the psychologist Rachel Herz shows, in That’s Disgusting: Unraveling the Mysteries
of Repulsion, we each have a culturally learned hostility to disgusting
sensations, because these tend to remind us of our mortality of which we’re
terrified, and thus we associate them with poisonous foods against which a universal
form of disgust evolved as a warning mechanism. For example, however
politically incorrect this reaction might be, a malformed human body revolts us
because the offending spectacle shows that we’re produced by mindless natural
forces with which we can’t sympathize. Our sense of physical beauty is also
instinctive, evolving not just as the complement of our fear of ugliness, but
as a way of measuring the fitness of a potential mate, given certain outward
indicators of health such as symmetric, average, and youthful facial features
and proportionality in waist-hip ratio. In either case, the individual rather
than the group is central to the aesthetic sense--although indirectly the
question of genetic fitness bears on the health of future generations. Second,
there’s the modern aesthetic preference for originality over the cliché.
Again, this distinction is about the individual, not the group--in this case,
about individual achievement; indeed, the ideal of originality is the
antisocial one of overcoming social pressures, including popular standards and
all manner of received wisdom, and daring to be different, to heroically pursue
a creative vision.
Now, were you to try to rationally support your preference
for beauty or for originality, entering your judgment as the conclusion of a
logical argument or a scientific experiment, you’d run up against the naturalistic
fallacy just as in the case of a moral judgment. For example, you’d have to
cite the fact that we have an inborn distaste for certain sensations and thus
naturally incline to their opposites, and then you’d have to call a halt to the
proceedings since no normative or value-laden statement follows just from such
a factual one. However, the intrusion of reason into the aesthetic sphere is
arbitrary in a way that it isn’t in the moral one, and so there’s no
self-destructive dialectic in the former as there is in the latter. There’s no
need to rationally prove the merit of an aesthetic preference, just as there’s
no need to compare the taste of an apple to that of an orange. Taking up an
aesthetic perspective is just the having of a taste for certain sensations and
a primitive opposition to others, the putting aside of our empirical
understanding of something as we attend to its surface features and to their
subjective impact on us; thus we distinguish between beauty and ugliness. In
the case of clichés, we hope for progress in the future and, buoyed by the
undeniable advances in science and technology, we’re ashamed of backwards
institutions that bind geniuses in red tape; we prefer originality as a sign of
insight or vision and we loathe cliché as an indicator of somnolence.
How Aesthetics Can Replace Morality
How, then, does aesthetics bear on morality? Well, if we put
aside the preoccupation with the goal of unifying society, we can recover moral
distinctions in aesthetic terms. Take, for example, the prohibition of parasitic
behaviour, including murder, theft, rape, and so on. All such behaviours are
viscerally disgusting, if nothing else, because they involve violence or sadden
the victim, and the sight of blood, tears, or facial expressions of pain alert
us to our mortality and thus arouse our primal fear of death. Moreover, parasitic
behaviour counts as clichéd, because it blindly follows low-level natural law.
A parasitic person resorts to trickery, calculating, in effect, that he can
preserve his genes best by exploiting the docility of those who play by
society’s rules, if only the parasite is sufficiently sneaky to avoid getting
caught. More generally, parasitism follows the iron-clad biological principle
that the vicious abuse the docile.
What’s original, morally speaking? One answer seems to be
this, rebellion against nature, as demonstrated by mystical ascetics and by
so-called omegas (“dysfunctional,” antisocial drop-outs). Of course,
defined broadly enough, everything in the universe is natural, so there’s no
unnatural behaviour. But the freedom to refuse to play the evolutionary game,
on some level at least, is a surprising development, placing personal integrity
and a unique sense of propriety above biological or social function. Again,
defined broadly, everything that happens in society, including the partial or
complete dropping out thereof, fulfills some social role. But in a more
interesting sense, ascetics, drop-outs, or at least jaded and apathetic
postmodernists are socially dysfunctional, threatening social collapse with
their skepticism and misanthropy, because they’re disenchanted with the promise
of what they regard as inauthentic happiness from the assimilation of consensus
reality. Instead of succumbing to pressures from biological urges or from the
Matrix of conventional wisdom, these rebels dare to risk public disapproval and
to sacrifice those pleasures that require ignorance, opposing the whole world
like Job who called God down from his throne to account for the apparent
injustice within Creation.
This latter biblical allusion shows the need to distinguish
between what we might call theological and philosophical aesthetics. The story
of Job is theological in that the bulk of it assumes the exoteric,
anthropocentric perspective, according to which there’s a personal cause of
nature who can be blamed in the first place. The story ends with a hint of the
esoteric, philosophical viewpoint, namely that of mysterianism or cosmicism, according
to which people aren’t central to the universe. Thus, God humiliates Job by
insulting him in his littleness and in his ignorance of the inhuman plan that
any being capable of creating the cosmos would likely devise. Of course, a
full-blown cosmicist tale, such as one penned by H. P. Lovecraft, would
dispense with a personal First Cause altogether and really rub our noses in our
cosmic insignificance.
I raise this point because a modern aesthetic reconstruction
of morality should value originality, identifying the latter with the
progressive genius that artistically overcomes the horror of appreciating our existential predicament. A traditional, theological reconstruction, however, might also
celebrate originality while defining the latter as anything made in God’s
image, in which case moral behaviour becomes that which is godlike. But
originality isn’t simply rarity. The problem with a theological conception of
our creativity is that this creativity is highly limited since we must each
conform to God’s revealed plan. Even God’s creativity is often thought to be
limited by his moral nature. At any rate, the theological notion of originality
is opposed to the modern one, since the latter always allows for the
possibility that contravening a tradition is progressive.
The point, then, is that the aesthetic distinction between
originality and cliché captures the difference between heroic independence and
conformity, which in turn can be used to reconstruct basic moral values. This
doesn’t mean that a shift from a moral to an aesthetic perspective on normative
questions is arbitrary or superficially semantic. On the contrary, morality’s
social context means that someone who thinks in (theologically or
scientistically) moral terms will be partial to conservative values,
whereas someone with a modern aesthetic perspective, at least, favours liberal,
progressive, and indeed antisocial ones. This isn’t to say that an aesthetic
moralist preys on the traditional one, since as I said, the aesthetic ideal
precludes predatory behaviour. But unlike morality, aesthetics also devalues
conformity and compromise for group welfare; it’s just that, while a predator
refuses to compromise when satisfying his base, clichéd and thus aesthetically
repellent desires, an aesthetic moralist prioritizes his personal pursuit of a
creative vision above any need for moderation for the sake of preserving
socially useful delusions.
To see how this works, let’s take the example of altruism (and see also these case studies).
Morally speaking, selflessness is justified because God, Reason, or natural
function commands it. Either way, there’s a moral rule which everyone in
society needs to follow. This framework breaks down with the rise of science,
once scientific knowledge came to be contrasted with all other contenders; in
particular, the rational defenses of moral imperatives convince no one but
cloistered academic philosophers, and the actual reigning values in a
postmodern capitalistic society aren’t just antisocial; they’re the grim social
Darwinian preconceptions of vain, duped consumers and of sociopathic oligarchs.
The public outcry against Wall Street stems not from moral opposition but from
jealousy or from fear of being the victim rather than the ruthless winner in
the prevailing wild competition between selfish agents.
So what would the aesthetic moralist, which is to say
someone who replaces moral with aesthetic reasoning, say about altruism? On the
one hand, self-sacrifice for someone else’s benefit can be clichéd, especially
if it follows straightforwardly from evolutionary theory. Moreover,
theistically motivated charity is hideous when it brings to mind the thought of
God, the latter being a transparent strategy for dealing with the fear of our
mortality. And yet the value of helping others follows from the ideal of
originality when the latter is construed as that of rebellion. After all, the
motivation for avoiding clichés, for being creative rather than conforming, is
disgust for what passes for normal. There would be no reason to progress were
the present state of affairs ideal, and it’s because someone with an artistic
frame of mind is appalled by so much in nature that he or she is driven to
create something superior. But someone who’s antagonistic to so much of what’s normal
is bound to pity fellow victims of those commonplace abuses, and that pity will
motivate the person to be altruistic. So whether the aesthetic defense of moral values preserves
altruism depends on how the altruistic act is motivated and performed.
Another difference between the moralistic and the aesthetic
approach to how we should live is found in the general outlooks. A moralist
views a person as a follower of socially useful rules. Modern morality is
scientistic and so obscures the difference between a rule and a natural law,
giving morality the appearance of being scientific. By contrast, an aesthetic
moralist sympathizes with a person as a victim of some degree of suffering who
copes best by interpreting her actions as artworks. Artists are known
for their civil disobedience, but when moral values are understood as merely
aesthetic, all human endeavours are viewed from an artistic perspective. At her
best, an artist is a creative genius, obeying not political compromises, but
her inner voice, her flashes of insight that provide her a vision of what ought
to be.
This is the essence of personal and social progress: such
progress depends not on the technoscientific standard of control, but on faith
in the rightness of inspired novelty, on the prospect that an uplifting and
comforting home for poor humans can emerge even in a universe of horribly undead natural forces. By elevating society above the individual, the
moralist restrains genius, turning the individual into a conformist. (Even
Kant, who did much to illuminate human autonomy, says in effect that the
individual is bound by the dictates of the general form of Reason which is
common to everyone.) Because our existential situation is absurd and tragic,
blind obedience ultimately to the avoidable evolutionary processes that set the
stage for our suffering is as disgraceful as the treachery of those Jewish kapos
who gained favour with the Nazis by collaborating with them in concentration
camps. The wrongness of conforming to natural norms, which traditional moral
rules tend to rationalize, is perceivable from an all-encompassing aesthetic
perspective, from the sense that compromising with society against your inner
creative promptings is distasteful.
If deluding ourselves to ignore the harsh reality of our existential situation is cliched, then how can avoiding ugliness because it reminds us of our mortality be an aesthetic virtue?
ReplyDeleteIn my view, avoiding ugliness can indeed be bad in the aesthetic sense, especially if the avoidance isn't based on any creative vision, but proceeds merely by conforming to social norms that degrade us. The ideal isn't just to avoid ugliness, but to overcome it, to face up to our mortality and to sublimate the horror we feel by creating for ourselves an original life, one that doesn't so straightforwardly serve our biological functions or social expectations based on obsolete myths.
DeleteMy point about disgust is that this instinctive response is a root of moral judgments. How we channel that feeling determines whether we're living with any aesthetic taste. So beauty isn't that which avoids ugliness at all costs, even by cowardly means such as deluding ourselves that we're really immortal. On the contrary, the theistic gambit is now one of the primary cliches.
Beauty is that which is seen in light of an imaginative ideal that deals heroically with our finitude and with the rest of our existential plight. Beauty is subjective and changes depending on the myths and values a person brings to bear. I take the moral task to be transcending ugliness by creating artworks in our minds and in our life decisions, artworks that overcome the undeadness of our bodies and of our beastly functions, reversing natural facts through ascetic rebellion. For more on the last point, see this article:
http://rantswithintheundeadgod.blogspot.ca/2013/04/technoscience-existentialism-and-fact.html
Hi Ben.
ReplyDeleteWhere in your view does the use of pornography and the act of masturbation fall into? Would you consider these as unoriginal responses to our existential situation?
Well, I've written something on pornography (link below). I have more to say on that subject, specifically on the addiction and downward spiral aspects, and on the peculiar way fetishists try to recapture the magic of their introduction to more and more perverted types of sex, by using descriptions to remind themselves of that moment. As I see it, porn is a sort of trap like any addiction.
DeleteAs for masturbation, it just falls into the sex category for me. I'm not telling people to stop expressing their sexual urges in any way. Obviously, people's sex lives are none of my business. My blog is about possible ideals for naturalists and social outsiders. It's hard to say what the ideal is for dealing with sex. Is it complete abstinence, because any form of happiness is grotesque in the midst of so much suffering in the world? Not really, because I suspect it's quite unhealthy to not release the pent-up fluids, just as it would be unhealthy (and impossible) to hold your urine in on a permanent basis.
What interests me more are the attitudes and intentions that go along with our behaviour. I'm not saying that existentially authentic people have to be constantly miserable. On the contrary, comedy is a big part of my worldview, as is artistic joy. But those with esoteric understanding are likely going to have their joys sullied by dark thoughts that keep creeping up. It's a matter of keeping the tragic big picture somewhere in the back of your mind, no matter what you're doing. However you understand that picture should inform what you decide to do with yourself, and this will depend on your particular inclinations and background.
Maybe you're getting at the possible originality of masturbation as a substitute for sex. The thing is, though, there are a million creative ways to have sex itself, as demonstrated by internet porn. What annoys me about sexual pleasure is that many people don't feel bad about the rank hypocrisy of indulging in their humiliating animal urges and then going to work in their business suits and acting like civilized custodians of the planet who are above it all. I'd just like to see more honesty and self-awareness. But the downside of losing that delusion is that you're going to have worse sex or perhaps none at all.
http://rantswithintheundeadgod.blogspot.ca/2013/05/polygyny-porn-stashes-and-clash-of.html