Is there a relationship between clinical anxiety and
existential angst? If so, what existential role do psychiatrists play in
treating anxiety disorders? I’ll address these and related questions in what
follows.
Anxiety Disorders
“Anxiety,” meaning a displeasing feeling of fear and concern
that causes worry, uneasiness, or dread as well as physical symptoms like
fatigue and concentration problems is a blanket term in psychiatry covering a
number of mental disorders, including phobias, panic disorder,
obsessive-compulsive disorder, posttraumatic stress disorder, and social
anxiety disorder. According to Wikipedia, general anxiety disorder
“is characterized by excessive, uncontrollable and often irrational worry about
everyday things that is disproportionate to the actual source of worry” and
“often interferes with daily functioning, as individuals suffering GAD
typically anticipate disaster, and are overly concerned about everyday matters [as
opposed to more specific ones, as in the other anxiety disorders like PTSD or
SAD] such as health issues, money, death, family problems, friendship problems,
interpersonal relationship problems, or work difficulties.” Anxiety disorders
have physiological causes as well as treatments in the forms of cognitive
behavioural therapy and pharmaceutical drugs.
Let’s turn to the more specific anxiety disorder, OCD, which
Wikipedia says is “characterized by intrusive thoughts that produce
uneasiness, apprehension, fear, or worry; by repetitive behaviors aimed at
reducing the associated anxiety; or by a combination of such obsessions and
compulsions.” The article goes on to say, “Obsessions are thoughts that recur
and persist despite efforts to ignore or confront them. People with OCD
frequently perform tasks, or compulsions, to seek relief from obsession-related
anxiety.” For example, someone with OCD may fear that she’ll leave the lights
on after she leaves a room, and even though she can see herself flip the switch
and watch the lights go out, she won’t trust her eyes, because she’ll entertain
extreme doubts about what she sees or won’t trust her memories. So to allay the
fear she may perform an elaborate ritual, by flipping the light switch off and
on several times, perhaps attaching some magical significance to the number. People
with OCD feel the ritual “somehow either will prevent a dreaded event from
occurring, or will push the event from their thoughts.” The compulsions are
irrational and people with OCD even know that they’re irrational on an
intellectual level, in that there’s no well-supported theory explaining any
causal link between the rituals performed and the desired outcome. If a person
with OCD turns the lights off and on six times, there’s no scientific
significance of that number; faith in the number is just a superstition. And
even if the ritual successfully pushes the fear away, this is only temporary so
the compulsion is irrational also in the sense of being relatively ineffective
as a treatment.
As the Wikipedia article points out, normal people also have irrational fears and even obsessions, but
“people with OCD may attach extraordinary significance to the thoughts.” Moreover,
“Whether or not behaviors are compulsions or mere habit depends on the context
in which the behaviors are performed. For example, arranging and ordering DVDs
for eight hours a day would be expected of one who works in a video store, but
would seem abnormal in other situations. In other words, habits tend to bring
efficiency to one's life, while compulsions tend to disrupt it.” Indeed, the
DSM-IV definition of GAD says that to count as a
disorder, the anxiety must “cause clinically significant distress or impairment
in social, occupational, or other important areas of functioning,” besides
meeting certain other conditions.
According to the Wikipedia article on GAD, cognitive
behavioural therapy assumes a person with GAD has at least some of the
following defects: “cognitive avoidance, positive worry beliefs, ineffective
problem-solving and emotional processing, interpersonal issues, previous
trauma, intolerance of uncertainty, negative problem orientation, ineffective
coping, emotional hyperarousal, poor understanding of emotions, negative
cognitive reactions to emotions, maladaptive emotion management and regulation,
experiential avoidance, and behavioral restriction.” To correct these defects,
the therapy might involve these components: “self-monitoring, relaxation
techniques, self-control desensitization, gradual stimulus control, cognitive
restructuring, worry outcome monitoring, present-moment focus, expectancy-free
living, problem-solving techniques, processing of core fears, socialization,
discussion and reframing of worry beliefs, emotional skills training,
experiential exposure, psychoeducation, mindfulness and acceptance exercises.”
For OCD, one behavioural treatment is to train the person to
tolerate the anxiety by weaning her off of the ritual. Another treatment is called
“associative splitting,” meaning that the person imagines neutral or positive
associations to change her thought patterns so that she’ll lose interest in the
behaviour.
Clinical Anxiety and Existential Angst
Now, besides clinical anxiety, there’s what I’ll called existential angst. Whereas the worries felt by someone with a so-called anxiety disorder are about things over which we have at least some control, even if the person resorts to performing magic rituals to deal with the imagined threats, angst pertains to more fundamental conditions of human life. For example, an angst-ridden person feels horror about having a finite body which is doomed to die, about our animal nature as evidenced by our sexuality, about the universe’s apparent godlessness, and about the existence of evil and of nature’s indifference to our plights. Existential philosophers and theologians maintain that because this angst is both fundamental to human experience and intolerable to us, we avoid the fear and the horror by distracting ourselves, by preferring delusions to reality-based worldviews, and so by becoming existentially inauthentic: we cope with the unpleasant structural truths of our existence by developing vices of avoidance rather than virtues of sublimation.
I wonder whether there’s a relationship between the
so-called anxiety disorders and existential angst. Could the general and
specific anxieties be unconscious substitutes
for angst, as though angst were filtered for conscious consumption and turned
into more manageable fears? If so, this would explain the paradoxical nature of
clinical anxiety: on the one hand, anxiety is intolerable and inescapable,
meaning that the fear is severely unpleasant and at best delayed by the rituals;
on the other hand, the fear is localized even in GAD to something less
fundamental than the finitude of organic life. Anxieties seem like more manageable forms of angst. Even if
clinical anxieties have physiological causes, they may effectively provide
means of coping with angst, by distracting the person with more superficial
fears.
It’s important here to understand the scientific perspective
of psychiatry. Although psychiatric discourse drips with normative presumptions
and implications, there is an unbridgeable abyss between psychiatric theories
themselves and normative discourse, which is to say that the theories must be
solely about facts rather than any normative evaluation of them. So although
the raison d’etre of psychiatry and
of all medical sciences is to do good
for the patient, as opposed to merely discovering how the body or the mind
works with no thought to practical applications, psychiatrists must
avoid normative discourse as much as possible. Only in that way can psychiatrists
be perceived as having mastered the scientific skills of objectivity,
neutrality, professional detachment, rigorous handling of quantifications, and
so forth.
Thus, the DSM doesn’t say that anxiety is bad and must be cured for that normative
reason, but employs the euphemism that anxiety “impairs important areas of
functioning.” What is a function, in this context? In psychiatry, this word is
used as an equivocation to maintain psychiatry’s Janus-faced position. In
common parlance, the word refers to the intended purpose of something that’s
been intelligently designed as a means to achieving a goal. Thus, all
technologies have functions, which are just the works the technologies are
meant to carry out to be useful. A telephone’s traditional function is to permit
people to communicate even across long distances. A gun’s function is to serve
as a deadly weapon. When a telephone or a gun breaks and can no longer perform
those desired ends, the users regard those malfunctions as bad because they
interpret the desired ends as good. People want to communicate or to defend
themselves, and although we may be unwise in the work we think ought to be
performed, the context of technological functions is normative, because the
functions are intended by designers or
consumers whose values motivate them to build or to purchase the technologies.
Psychiatrists presuppose that sense of “function” but they
also lean on the word’s biological sense. A biological function is just a
naturally selected effect. For example, the heart’s function is to circulate
blood in an organism, and although the organism may prefer that that end be
carried out, the effect’s subjective rightness is irrelevant to the process of
natural selection. This is because, whereas humans create technologies, there
is no intelligent designer of organisms, according to modern biology. So if you
think of human health from the biological perspective, you must put aside your
thoughts about what we think is good or bad, because the genes and the
environment have no such thoughts and they’re the main biological causes of our
health.
If pressed on this equivocation, the psychiatrist will say
that she borrows her normative judgments from society. Thus, if someone’s anxiety is so severe that it prevents
her from being socially productive, the anxiety will be bad in the
cryptonormative sense of being disordered and dysfunctional. The rightness of human health depends on
social standards of normality, and when someone doesn’t fit well into her
society, doctors look for causes of that conflict and seek to change not society
but the patient. This is because the psychiatrist’s sole source of
normative judgment, which motivates the entire medical endeavour to help the
patient, is the social convention about what’s right or wrong.
As the Wikipedia article puts it, distinguishing between
(dysfunctional) compulsions and (normal) habits, “habits tend to bring
efficiency to one's life, while compulsions tend to disrupt it.” This
presupposes that efficiency is a social good. And what is efficiency?
Efficiency is the effectiveness of your selected means of achieving your
desired end. For example, if you want to build a bridge to support cars, but
you choose to build the bridge out of marshmallows, you’re not being efficient.
Thus, “efficiency” is virtually synonymous with “instrumental rationality,” in
this context. And the assumption is that we ought to try to achieve what we
desire, thus “maximizing out utility.” But what if our desires were bad? In
that case, efficiency would also be bad. Indeed, the psychiatrist assumes that
someone with a mental illness may have the wrong desires, in which case the ill
person shouldn’t strive to be efficient in satisfying them. Mental illness could
still disrupt a person’s overall efficiency, by preventing her from pursuing
some of her priorities since she must waste time dealing with the illness. But
this presupposes that efficiency isn’t the ultimate ideal and that some desires
are better than others.
Notice that when the psychiatrist sides with social
convention and tradition, she chooses to ignore the existential perspective. When
the existentialist is horrified by human norms, she’s reacting to the majority’s
consensus about how we should live, since the majority tends to be
existentially inauthentic, and so existential horror requires a social
outsider’s perspective. The existentialist is alienated from society, just as the
scientist is alienated from her personal preoccupations when she thinks
objectively about the mysteries in nature. The
existentialist rejects much of what society regards as normal, not because of
some personal quirk, but because she puts herself in nature’s alien shoes, as
it were, looking on all of us as we would be seen were the atoms and the stars
to have eyes to see and a mind to judge. And the existentialist concludes that
human norms themselves are absurd (objectively
meaningless). This is because the atoms and the stars have no eyes or mind, and
the existentialist’s alienation is self-destructive. What you appreciate when
you detach from social myths and traditions and nevertheless think about social
goings-on is that even our normal, much beloved practices are ridiculous games.
Just as we laugh at clowns when we’re outside the circus, so too
existentialists laugh at society generally when they detach from a culture’s assumptions
about what’s normal or good.
So the psychiatrist assumes that clinical anxiety is bad and
ought to be cured, because this anxiety prevents the person from fulfilling her
social functions--to use the quasi-scientific euphemism. In plain language,
someone with an anxiety disorder doesn’t do what society thinks she ought to be
doing, because she’s incapable of doing so without help. But from the
existential perspective, which is also the mystical perspective in
the esoteric traditions of most major religions as well as the perspective of
most introverts, social omegas, and modern artists, that very assessment
of what’s functional/good is suspect. The
psychiatrist stands with society and condemns those who would be social
outsiders if left to their own devices, while the existentialist stands with
horrible nature and condemns the norms
of human societies for being engines of existential inauthenticity. These engines
are ethically and aesthetically graceless means of dealing with the primary
facts of life. And in so far as a society is especially deluded and hostile to
existential virtues, the psychiatrist exacerbates the greater sin of
existential inauthenticity by reversing those people’s antisocial tendencies. By
“curing” someone of her inability to fit into society, she knocks down a
barrier that would have helped prevent society from indoctrinating the outsider with its
delusions and distractions.
The psychiatrist’s duplicity is especially apparent in her
double standard regarding OCD and mainstream religion. There is obviously no
way for the psychiatrist to condemn OCD and to give mainstream monotheism a
pass, without special pleading for the latter. Both the monotheist and the
person with OCD have obsessive fears which they alleviate with irrational
rituals. In the case of monotheism, these rituals include prayer, attending
Church, and studying an obsolete text that’s supposedly inspired by God.
Indeed, the Wikipedia article on OCD says that one of the common obsessions is
“the possibility that someone or something other than oneself--such as God, the
Devil, or disease--will harm either the person with OCD or the people or things
that the person cares about.” As quoted above, the article tries to allay
concerns that the obsessions of so-called normal people must likewise be
dysfunctional, thus undermining the psychiatric distinction, by saying that
dysfunctional obsessions are those to which “extraordinary significance” is
attached. Well now, how much significance should
be attached to the belief that there are all-seeing gods as well as demons
tempting people into sin so that our immortal spirits are damned to hell for
eternity? Surely, the religious fundamentalist’s obsession with these theistic
ideas is extraordinary compared to the religious moderate’s, but this in itself
is hardly a defect of fundamentalism. Some ideas call for extreme actions, so
just because a belief is common or ordinary doesn’t mean it’s well-justified.
This is why appealing to popularity can be fallacious.
But the reason the psychiatrist condemns OCD and not
mainstream religion is that the latter has been socially integrated. To be
sure, the psychiatrist’s quasi-scientific theory of OCD implies that most
monotheists ever born have suffered from “dysfunctional” anxiety in the form of
OCD. But psychiatry isn’t a pure science, because medical science has a
normative purpose, which is to say that medicine was technoscientific
from its inception, as opposed to being abstract theorizing with no regard to
social utility. The psychiatrist is supposed to act for the good, and she
chooses the ideals that are normal within her society, rather than thinking
through ethical matters on her own or siding with the antisocial findings of
existentialists, mystics, introverts, and so on. So if one form of OCD is
integral to a society, as it is in the case of manifestly irrational
monotheism, the psychiatrist can only resort to mental gymnastics when
defending the ideals she borrows from that sick society while condemning
antisocial forms of OCD. The psychiatrist borrows ideals that derive from one
form of mental illness (mainstream religion), to condemn a mental illness (OCD) that inoculates social
outsiders so that they won’t be subjected to the more prevalent illnesses and delusions. This
situation is just extravagantly absurd enough to be natural.
Some Red Herrings
Likewise, then, the fact that people with anxiety disorders
can be cured is neither here nor there, as far as my discussion is concerned. Normal,
healthy, socially acceptable people can also be “cured” of their normality, if
they’re brainwashed to accept a crazy belief system or if they’re convinced to
take mind-altering drugs. Abnormal people can be made normal and normal people
can be made abnormal, if certain steps are taken. This is a matter of there
being physical mechanisms operating in either direction, as it were, so we
don’t learn the normative status of something just because we know how to
physically change the thing into something else.
As for the insufferable pomposity of cognitive behavioural
therapists, we should keep in mind that this therapy combines behaviourism and
the cognitive revolution in psychology, and thus contemporary practitioners
inherit the arrogance of behaviourists who, decades ago, abstracted away the mind
so they could imagine they were reducing people and animals to machines that
could be trained. Since each behaviourist enjoyed a first-person perspective
only on her own thoughts, she came to feel superior to the animals and people
she studied in her lab, since she could more easily dehumanize bodies whose
internal states she couldn’t access more directly by introspection. As Horkheimer
and Adorno point out in Dialectic of
Enlightenment, it’s the Marquis de Sade who brings ultrarationality to fruition.
When you’re dealing with machines, the proper course is to modify them by
forceful programming or to use them as slaves. Behaviorists reduced all
creatures to machines simply by ignoring their minds and focusing on their observable
behaviours (stimulus and response patterns, and so on).
And so we shouldn’t be surprised to find the intellectual descendants
of those pretentious wannabe ultrarationalists saying in
Wikipedia that CBT’s premise is “that changing maladaptive
thinking leads to change in affect and in behavior.” The word “maladaptive”
here is a technical term in CBT and means unproductive or counterproductive.
Adaptive responses constructively deal with disruptive behaviour. Thus,
compulsive rituals in OCD are maladaptive since they’re inefficient and
disruptive, and so forth. However, from the existential perspective, antisocial
behaviour can be constructive if the society is in decline and the culture robs
you of your authenticity. Of course, changing thoughts can change behaviour,
assuming thoughts can cause behaviour. But the phony objectivity in the use of “maladaptive”
masks the CB therapist’s conservatism, since she sides with social conventions and
thus gives no credit to mental illnesses as adaptive/effective inoculators
against cultural nonsense (delusions, distractions, games, collective disorders,
and obsolete myths and other dogmas).
Again, quoting a medical article, Wikipedia says CB
therapists ‘help individuals challenge their patterns and beliefs and replace
"errors in thinking such as overgeneralizing, magnifying negatives,
minimizing positives and catastrophizing" with "more realistic and
effective thoughts, thus decreasing emotional distress and self-defeating
behavior.” ’ This talk of “errors in thinking” is straight out of the behaviourist
tradition of dehumanization, which in turn was foreshadowed by the Marquis de Sade.
Whatever mentally ill people do wrong, according to society, that wrongness isn’t
confined to any mere error of reasoning. On the contrary, as I’ve argued
elsewhere, the mentally ill are monstrous
for calling attention to the arbitrariness of social conventions. And whatever
the physiological causes of mental disorders, those who prefer not to be
treated may console themselves by reaping the benefits of being social outsiders.
So there may be a choice involved rather than just some error in computation. I
suspect that if you look into the CB theory behind this talk of errors in thinking, you’ll find a great deal of subjective, philosophical or even quasi-religious
normative presuppositions. Like the rest of us, wannabe ultrarationalists are mere mammals, after
all. Likewise, the talk of replacing those “errors” with “more realistic and
effective” thoughts is so much balderdash. CB therapists receive their
authority from social conventions which establish the norms against which the abnormal
behaviours of the mentally ill are judged bad. But social conventions are
rarely realistic; on the contrary, cultures are filled with delusions that
distract the majority from appreciating the natural, cosmicist reality which
defines our existential predicament.
Society Versus the Individual
I want to clarify what I think we are entitled to conclude from the above.
I’m not saying that people with anxiety disorders should be left alone. Within
the law, people are free to choose their goals, and if some genetic quirk
causes certain people to act in a way that prevents them from achieving those goals,
including the goal of fitting into society, those people should seek treatment.
Moreover, not every case of fitting into society is bad even in existential terms.
This depends on the society and on the degree of conformity. My point, then,
isn’t to condemn all psychiatry. Rather, what interests me is the big picture
in which psychiatry is caught up in the process of serving the majority’s collective
interests. Whether psychiatric practices are noble in the grand scheme depends
on whether the society itself is healthy or in decline. I suggested that
clinical anxiety may be a means of coping with existential angst, but even
if there’s no such connection, psychiatry looks different from a perspective
that acknowledges our dire existential situation. Psychiatrists typically
defend social norms and offer treatment for antisocial behaviours. But even
when these behaviours cause suffering, they’re also blessings in disguise if
they compel the person to detach from a society so she’s spared the downside of
being fully integrated into an existentially-flawed population.
The question that’s ignored by the psychiatrist’s talk of
“functioning” is whether a particular set of social norms is good or bad. If
you think all normative judgments derive from mass opinion, you’ll think this
question is unanswerable. But existentialists, mystics, artists,
introverts, romantics, and omegas disagree. They think the individual can envision her personal ideals and that even if she’s
influenced by her society, her vision stands as a more or less original work of
ideological art. So even if an anxiety disorder causes suffering, that
suffering should be balanced against the good done when the disorder detaches
the person from a potentially inferior culture. Siding always with the
social norms, as is the psychiatrist’s wont and as though all societies were
equally good, is philosophically very dubious. The complete assessment of a
mental disorder will consider both the social perspective, and thus the
psychiatric one which takes social norms/functions for granted, but also the antisocial
perspective as it’s found in philosophical and religious traditions.
Psychiatrists and social workers suspect that those
suffering from anxiety disorders (and from mental disorders generally)
underreport their conditions. One explanation of this is that there’s a social
stigma attached to the disorders, but I think this explanation is insufficient.
Assuming that mental disorders ostracize those who have them, these people are
forced to look at society anew (given that their critical faculties are left
intact by the disorder). Just as a game looks different depending on whether
you’re a player or a spectator, society looks different depending on whether
you take social conventions for granted or study them as an outsider. The
mentally ill tend to be social outsiders and so they’re well-positioned to
appreciate the absurdity of many social practices. Understandably, an ill
person will prefer not to suffer, and to that extent mainly the stigma would
prevent her from seeking treatment. But the mental illness may have the upside
of bestowing greater objectivity and that may help explain why mental illnesses
are underreported: the suffering
outsiders don’t want to be accepted by a culture they come to regard as
ridiculous. In some cases, antisocial attitudes may be the poisoned fruits
of a deranged mind, but in others the illness may force the person to look
objectively at society and at human nature, and as is apparent from the history
of modern science, objectivity is toxic to dogmas.
PostScript: Evolution and the Self-Destruction of Omegas
An article summarizing a number of recent books on the widely-reported anxiety epidemic in the US concludes, “American anxiety seems like a cultural chimera created by, yes, social and economic problems, and by personal crises, but also by media attention.” The summarized books point to specific causes of anxiety in the US, such as the pressures of academia and the invention of Prozac-like drugs by Big Pharma. Certainly, the existential predicament I talk about doesn’t explain all kinds of anxiety, although some social and economic factors are related to our intense modern awareness of that predicament.
Kahn’s explanation looks to me like it takes on the
perspective not just of the genes, but of society’s winners. The winners and
the best guardians and proliferators of the gene pool might prefer to think
that the omegas withdraw because the losers recognize the superiority of the other
members and bow out by suffering from sort of anxiety or depression. The
anxiety becomes a physiological mechanism that eliminates those who are no
longer socially useful, but the point is that this is supposed to be an active
self-withdrawal for the good of the group. I think this reverses cause and effect. Anxiety and depression don’t cause the social withdrawal of omegas;
rather, the cause is the omegas’ relative weakness or introversion which in
turn causes them to lose in competition with stronger group members, so that
the pecking order forms in an organic way. Anxiety and depression are effects of being on the outside of a
society. When you’re alienated from a society, you can afford to look on it
objectively, in which case you recognize the arbitrariness and absurdity of its
rules and practices; you lack a social network and the distractions of cultural
games, giving you time to ruminate and philosophize, which leads to skepticism,
atheism, a greater sensitivity to suffering, and a general appreciation of our
existential plight.
PostScript: Evolution and the Self-Destruction of Omegas
An article summarizing a number of recent books on the widely-reported anxiety epidemic in the US concludes, “American anxiety seems like a cultural chimera created by, yes, social and economic problems, and by personal crises, but also by media attention.” The summarized books point to specific causes of anxiety in the US, such as the pressures of academia and the invention of Prozac-like drugs by Big Pharma. Certainly, the existential predicament I talk about doesn’t explain all kinds of anxiety, although some social and economic factors are related to our intense modern awareness of that predicament.
But I’d like to talk about an evolutionary explanation of melancholic
depression by Jeffrey Kahn, summarized in the article. The explanation is that depression
could have evolved as a means of weeding out unproductive members of a group,
to conserve the group’s scarce resources. The old and infirm members would withdraw
from society, sacrificing themselves for the good of the group and giving the
stronger, more promising members a larger share of the food, weapons, and other
goods. Howard Blum offers a similar explanation of self-destruction in The Lucifer Principle. However, there’s
a better evolutionary explanation, which is that a dominance hierarchy forms
not because the omegas direct how the group is structured, but because they’re
not strong enough to compete with the alphas and betas, and the stronger
members bully their way to a greater share of the resources. Genetically, the
result is the same since the resources are reserved for the group’s stronger
members, but the social mechanism is different: the omegas don’t choose to
sacrifice themselves for the good of the majority, but are naturally pushed out
by the stronger members in a competition.
Like the comparison between human DNA and chimpanzee DNA, your philosophy is almost all of Saint Fond's, except that you vary it at the very tip of the helix so as to find meaning, or at least a form of beauty, in opposing everything up to that point, which has been admittedly horrendous.
ReplyDeleteMental health professionals have, throughout what we might call western civilization, been essentially the "psychiatrists" you now describe. Their function is to maintain social order by decreasing healthy reactions to negative conditions, and increasing acceptance and the performance of labor. Of necessity, they would seem to be blind, but the best duckspeakers are always those who understand, simultaneously, truth and fiction. So too with physicians (and "specialist" psychiatrists), who can be divided into groups of those who earnestly believe in what they're peddling (stupid), those who understand the game and feel that it is right (evil), and those who think they can effect some small positive change through direct patient interaction (mistaken--probably).
Anecdotally, this one has noticed that most physicians understand that the real purpose of drugs, from caffeine to more profitable pharmaceuticals, is to tape broken bodies together long enough that they can keep punching clocks or fulfilling ("mere") social obligations. Even at the level of, say, Michael Jackson or Heath Ledger, the need to drug together a shell in order to exploit it in the jungle exists, and these very educated, occasionally intelligent doctors recognize that their livelihoods depend on despondent populations continuing to live in despondent structures. They're just mechanics in an endless supercar race, rarely bothering to wonder why so many crashes and explosions happen.
Yet another example set of clueless (or evil) people, in pursuit of illusions, and so causing others to suffer. The simple conclusion is, again, St. Fond's, or a version of "take what you can get"--whether orgies or philosophical superiority; name your pleasure. St. Fond probably arrived at the more sensible place, given how much you have in common, for an awareness of how cold materialism must be.
If you're talking about the character Saint Fond from Sade's book Juliette, I don't think our philosophies are the same. He's a libertine, whereas I explore a modern ascetic kind of ethics. He thinks selfish pleasure is justified no matter what the cost to others, so that even murder is justified in the pursuit of such pleasure. I base my values on pity for everyone stuck in the same existential predicament and on disgust for cliches like existential inauthenticity. My point about Sade wasn't that I agree with libertinism, but that libertinism follows from pre-Nietzschean Enlightenment Scientism. But yes, we share certain modern assumptions, and Sade and I try to make the best of them in very different ways.
DeleteI think your conspiracy theory about American psychiatrists is plausible. However, I'm sure many social workers and doctors are struck by the great suffering of many people, and their reductive technoscience offers mainly drug treatments. Mental illnesses are quite real in the sense that the brain can produce all sorts of abnormal behaviour, much of which causes suffering in various social contexts. The question I think a psychiatrist would ask is whether there's some better way of dealing with all of this suffering. Eastern medicine? New Age spiritual treatments? Another interesting question to me is whether the modern lifestyle causes some of these mental disorders, like schizophrenia, or whether they're universal.
Well, a lot of information here.
ReplyDeleteThe post above remained me of depressive realism:
From Wikipedia
“Studies by psychologists Alloy and Abramson (1979) and Dobson and Franche (1989) suggested that depressed people appear to have a more realistic perception of their importance, reputation, locus of control, and abilities than those who are not depressed.
People with depression may be less likely to have inflated self-images and look at the world through "rose-colored glasses", thanks to cognitive dissonance elimination and a variety of other defense mechanisms that allow them to ignore or otherwise look beyond the harsh realities of life.”
As a sufferer of depression I have often wandered along the same lines. Eventually I arrived at the conclusion that depression is a consequence of seeing the world as it really is as opposed to what we might wish it to be. So, is the cure for depression delusional thinking? You bet it is.
InNterestingly, according to Wikipedia, those with OCD also have above-average intelligence.
DeleteDelusional thinking is certainly the mainstream way out of depressing realism. I'm looking for another way. I think we should start by interpreting deep philosophical ideas as so many artworks made out of words, memories, feelings, and logical relations. That's a realistic view of metaphysics and of theology, which runs against our inclination to be dogmatic, and this view also allows us to find meaning in those ideas that move us, to create myths even we jaded postmodernists can believe in.
I thought this might be relevant to the topic. I think each of us is unique and should be treated so. When one suffers from anxiety that is debilitating physically and mentally, a few meds is not going to change you. After a long period of anxiety which I have experienced and am experiencing now, a depression usually follows. I'm not sure if I could call my perceptions more real than any other person. I think the realism is unique to the individual. It is just as real as any other. When one is in this depressed state it can be relentless and destructive to their practical life. As Ben says YOU MUST KEEP WORKING. YOU MUST GET FIXED. Take some of these and these and then some more. It can feel like you are being pulled in two directions at once. And the thing which I think can bring the body and mind into harmony is the acceptance of emptiness. I wrote about this on one of your other blogs but I forgot to reply. You asked whether this emptiness is more common in a western culture? I think it is more common since we have a tremendous amount external satisfaction. I think when our cup overflows we experience an existential problem. This can be ignored by more booze or prayer or sex or whatever you want. But this fatigue that I have experienced after attaining my desires and psychological security; identity, status, financial or whatever, I am confronted by this emptiness and I don't want to live with it. Coming to realize that who I am is a joke. And the circumstances that led me here are as chaotic as the wind and this whole concept of progression and success and normality in this society is so backwards it makes me so bitter. So what is one to do?
ReplyDeleteThomas Merton on the Dark Night of the Soul
ReplyDelete“During the ‘dark night’ of the feelings and senses, anxiety is felt in prayer, often acutely. This is necessary, because this spiritual night marks the transfer of the full, free control of our inner life into the hands of a superior power. And this too means that the time of darkness is, in reality, a time of hazard and of difficult options. We begin to go out of ourselves: that is to say, we are drawn out from behind our habitual and conscious defenses. These defenses are also limitations, which we must abandon if we are to grow. But at the same time they are, in their own way, a protection against the unconscious forces that are too great for us to face naked and without protection.
“If we set out into this darkness, we have to meet these inexorable forces. We will have to face fears and doubts. We will have to call into question the whole structure of our spiritual life. We will have to make a new evaluation of our motives for belief, for love, for self-commitment to the invisible God. And at this moment, precisely, all spiritual light is darkened, all values lose their shape and reality, and we remain, so to speak, suspended in the void.
“The most crucial aspect of this experience is precisely the temptation to doubt God himself. We must not minimize the fact that this is a genuine risk. For here we are advancing beyond the stage where God made himself accessible to our mind in simple and primitive images. We are entering the night in which he is present without any image, invisible, inscrutable, and beyond any satisfactory mental representation.
“At such a time as this, one who is not seriously grounded in genuine theological faith may lose everything he ever had. His prayer may become an obscure and hateful struggle to preserve the images and trappings which covered his own interior emptiness. Either he will have to face the truth of his emptiness or else he will beat a retreat into the realm of images and analogies which no longer serve for a mature spiritual life. He may not be able to face the terrible experience of being apparently without faith in order to really grow in faith. For it is this testing, this fire of purgation, that burns out the human and accidental elements of faith in order to liberate the deep spiritual power in the center of our being. This gift of God is, of itself, unattainable, but is given to us moment by moment, beyond our comprehension, by his inscrutable mercy.”
-- Thomas Merton, Contemplative Prayer, pp. 77-78
Just replace 'God' with 'Undead God'. X-D
ReplyDeleteThanks for this quotation, Stephen. I'm not so sure we can just replace "God" with "undead god," though. There's an interesting article I recently read on the topic of how much suffering we can take. Here's the link:
Deletehttp://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2013/04/07/the-light-at-the-end-of-suffering/
This article takes up William James's view of the stages of misery, which turn out to be similar to the 12-step program. In each case, as in Merton here, the sticking point is that we've got to surrender our ego to a higher power. The power doesn't have to be a personal God, but my point is that I think it makes a difference whether this power is personal or not. I'll have to think about this some more and I'll likely write about this when I lay out my existential cosmicist case against suicide.
HAHA. Of course. I think Merton was an enlightened man. When he speaks of God he is not speaking of the common Christian God. Undead God doesn't make sense really.
DeleteMaybe like Jung's process of individuation? I'm an idiot with this stuff. I am still trying to find my path and understand these concepts. All I have to go on is my own observation.
I'll go read that article.
Thanks Ben!
You're right that Merton was an enlightened fellow, mixing Eastern and Western traditions. In a week or two I'm going to write more about this idea of surrendering to a higher power.
DeleteThanks Ben I can't wait. Also this process of surrendering to a higher power is part of the 12 steps in AA. I have a friend who was attending these meetings for some time. He asked me to come along. I found that there are people who are so desperate that they really need that higher power. My friend on the other hand who was practicing Buddhist meditation for some time told me that going to these meetings helped him to come off booze for over a year. Unfortunately he relapsed after he discovered what I had warned him about. Because AA is sort of Christian group it's easy to get entangled in the dubiousness of any institution that offers salvation through 12 steps. He discovered that there was a a lot of fundamentalism in AA and since it was based on Christian faith and an autocratic universe, it was parallel to the non dual concept in Buddhism.
DeleteThere are so many traps we can fall into. I believe that any kind of transformation is going to be painful. Arka said that we should use reason to lead us to more pleasant conclusions about the universe. I agree with this to an extent. But reason is what got us into this mess. Obviously we need it to get out of it. That's the paradox isn't it? If we surrender to a higher power surely this requires one to go through a painful process and face this emptiness of having no faith or no identity to truly transform. Before we surrender what do we have to go through and what are the traps that we fall into?
I'm looking forward to your article on this subject.
Peace.
Steve
Mr. Cain, what could be more libertine in the postindustrial west than asceticism? We dwell in the clutches of the women and men Sade described, and your rejection of their mores is very similar, in form, to Fond's rejection of the mores of the Ancien Regime and the Consulate: which is to say, it is not a rejection, but an affirmation.
ReplyDeleteFond acted as though spurning society, and may actually have believed it, but Sade was far too clever; he consistently demonstrated how the material world was ruled by men like Fond. The characteristic of morality is contrary to the strictly material world, while the downfall of the silent masses (and Justine) is, to Fond, in believing that the morality Fond "rejects" is meant as anything more than a tool to exploit the population.
More importantly, Sade showed how materialism combined with rationality leads inexorably to the plots of his villains.
Your pleasures are different than Fond's, however the initial metaphor between human DNA compared to chimpanzee DNA was meant to illustrate how very similar are the paths you two traveled. When you "reject" modern society, and conclude that joy is delusion and nature undead, you're affirming the real tenets of society. You are, like Fond, expressing better the nature of this affliction than any true believer could, because the true believer would actually fall for things like the pursuit of happiness via material goods--and, so, would be missing the real point, which is that suffering is inescapable.
An irony in your initial argument is the mass depression itself. That depression is a healthy reaction to the horrors of modern society, indicating in part that the human mind is rejecting the emptiness and death of the bland and material. If we saw that mass depression paired with a paradisiacal world, then we might conclude--like Agent Smith--that humans are meant to be miserable.
(Agent Smith's conclusion is, incidentally, one of the greatest crimes of the filthy thieves who perverted Ghost in the Shell into a sort-of-related western blockbuster: to turn its message of hope and deeper meaning into a vaguely oracular neo-Christian electron hell.)
Depression in the face of modernity is hope. Drugs and psychiatrists are the attempt to fool the world.
(Continued for length.)
I see that I should write something on the relation between Sade's libertinism and my view; moreover, I think this will be an epic article, so I thank you for pressing this issue.
DeleteA clarification: I say that happiness is unbecoming/tasteless, not that it's a delusion. (Here's a thought experiment: what would we say about someone who's merry in a room full of miserable people? Well, most people suffer a lot, so to make personal contentment your highest aim is just grotesque in that context.) I say that delusions are needed for happiness, but the happiness itself can be real.
On the Matrix, I too don't care for the Christian pandering, especially in the third movie, although the Gnostic themes are compelling. I think the movie Dark City was another influence. I haven't seen Ghost in the Shell, but I've read a few other series by Shirow. His characters talk a lot.
"The question I think a psychiatrist would ask is whether there's some better way of dealing with all of this suffering."
ReplyDeleteThe psychiatrist cannot ask this question openly, or the psychiatrist ceases to be a licensed physician, and becomes instead a political radical, dangerous to the profession as well as to society at large.
To fairly address modern mental disorders would mean to criticize the planet's rulers. It would mean urging the dismantlement and rebuilding of the nation's economies, and an end to the powerless sale of surplus labor to the inheriting genes of old. It would mean telling people that their problems are not their fault, but are a healthy reaction, and telling them to heal by avoiding drugs and therapy, and instead to revolt, commit suicide, or otherwise remove themselves from a system of exploitation.
No psychiatrist can do that with her patients, or she would be swiftly disciplined, put out of the profession, and left to complain on the internet. It is permissible to tell someone to leave an abusive husband, but not to leave an abusive nation-state--the latter advise is irresponsible quackery.
5:05 Anonymous, studies of depression tend to be hard to randomize, because people who volunteer for medical studies tend to be either:
1) People afflicted by the condition being studied, or;
2) Poorer people trying to make a few bucks by participating in a study.
As a result, it is very hard to find a fair sampling that would not skew any set of results toward viewing the afflicted set as, on the average, more intelligent--since comparing a random sampling of the population to a low-income sampling of the population will almost always produce distinct differences in multiple-choice test results.
Another extreme difficulty for professionally studying a mental disorder is how many people have the disorder and never report it: not only to professionals, but even to family members, the very closest of friends, or the individual herself.
For example, how many Christians privately doubt the existence of God in the last year (week? hour?) of their lives? How many would answer the question honestly?
(To Mr. McGuire's question about what one is to do, an answer might be the use of reason to lead to more realistic and pleasant conclusions about existence. If we're to be depressed, it can be an empathetic depression that recognizes its own place within the system.)
You are on fire, sir. This post was a cold glass of water in the desert.
ReplyDeleteThanks very much, William.
DeleteThis is very good information.i think it's useful advice. really nice blog. keep it up!!!
ReplyDelete- psychiatry salem ma