Do miracles happen? Is the notion of the miraculous still
useful, after the Scientific Revolution? I think so, contrary to the strawman originating,
perhaps, from David Hume’s criticisms of natural theology. Hume misconceived of
miracles as violations of natural law, defining “natural law” as an inductive
generalization that’s based on observations of mere correlations between events.
We perceive loose patterns in the world and add causal connections via the
imposition of instinctive expectations or heuristics (cognitive rules of thumb)
onto the more open-ended data. We thus naturally simplify the world’s infinite
complexity to make rational sense of it, as opposed to wishing the world
operated according to the gratuitous, occult dictates of divine commandments.
Natural laws are thus opposed to religious dogmas, for example, in that the
former are based on the brain’s interpretive mechanisms, whereas the stem from strategies
for social domination.
This Humean view is right as far as it goes, but it’s not
sufficiently atheistic. There are no objective natural laws, since “law” in this
case is euphemistic. There are regularities which we understand according to our
models which simplify and idealize to further such pragmatic ends as our
interest in exploiting apparent natural processes. But all laws are social agreements, given atheism rather than deism or
theism. Strictly speaking, there are no
natural laws and thus there can be no violations of them. Thus, the notion of a miracle as a
violation of a natural law is useless. Here, though, is a worthwhile notion
of a miracle: a miracle is an anomaly that astonishes or terrorizes those who
appreciate something of the strange event’s significance. Notice that this
definition is consistent with the foregoing account of natural order. Again,
there are perceived regularities which are understood in light of our
subjective and social resources, including our cognitive rules of thumb and
experimental models. The regularities themselves are objective, as are the data
that inform our models, but the way we understand and explain the phenomena are
largely anthropocentric. Even scientific understanding, which bypasses the
crude anthropocentrism in the metaphors implicit in natural language, inherits
the animal’s prejudice for the utility of working tools or traits. The chief
standard for scientific explanations is their workability in the civilized
project of taming the natural world. Like all gross, bullying demonstrations of
power, technoscience will likely prove to be self-destructive. In any case, we
become accustomed to the regularities we observe, because we’re in terror
mainly of what we don’t understand. Anomalies,
then, are those natural events which are rare and which we don’t understand.
Some subset of anomalies is, further, miraculous, because a philosophical suspicion
of its cosmic importance subverts the predominant way of life.
There have been at least three miracles in this viable sense.
First, there was the proto-physical event that sparked the universe’s creation
from quantum weirdness rather than from any intelligent design. Virtual
nothingness proved to be unstable and so particles popped spontaneously into
being. Then the seed inflated and evolved into spacetime which fragmented into
the galaxies of solar systems we see today. Second, life developed from
nonlife. At one time, physical processes occurred despite there being no one to
wonder at them. Some such processes created a rudimentary form of biological
life, and that life form complexified by natural selection and by other such
evolutionary means so that organisms acquired various body types, including
senses and brains for interpreting the environment. Third, some organisms
developed also a vision of how the world should be and boldly sought to modify
how the world naturally is, according to that ideal.
The Miracle of Artificiality
Let’s focus on the third miracle, which is the miracle of
artificiality, of art and of all other idealistic contrivances. Part of this
miracle is present in the way the natural patterns of some system persist
despite interference from the system’s environment. This is why working
explanatory models are ceteris paribus,
why they include some humble recognition of the model’s limitations or
partiality. The model is about a special occurrence that “tends” to happen but
that may or may not actually happen, depending on the circumstances. In the
laboratory, those circumstances are controlled for, so the phenomenon can be
studied in isolation and in its pristine form, whereas in the wild, factors
which aren’t covered by the model can intervene and prevent the causal
relationship from materializing. There are, then, possible outcomes, one of which speaks, as it were, to what we
think of as nature’s structure, to some signal or meaningful bit of
information, whereas the other outcomes are so many confounding noises. Only a
theory of the totality of the universe would bypass the need for this
distinction between system and environment, between the part and the whole, in
which case the places of every part would be understood according to their interrelations
that make up the whole of everything; more precisely, the whole would be
understood as a unity with no divisible parts.
As to why one possibility is realized rather than another in
nature, this is typically accidental. At least, there’s no intelligent
direction or choice as to when the effect follows the cause as dictated by a
scientific idealization. Peripheral conditions may or may not impede the
unfolding of some segment of natural structure. Sometimes they do, sometimes
they don’t, depending on which way the wind is blowing. Mystical rationalists
such as Plato like to think that nature’s mathematical structure is objectively
ideal, that some natural developments are closer to the Good than others. But
if there’s no Mind responsible for nature, there can be no such purely
objective good, neither in a moral nor in an aesthetic sense. What there can be
is the potential for a meeting between the observed and the observer, which is
bound to strike the latter as having one value rather than another. For
example, from an artistic perspective, some natural outcomes may seem beautiful,
not disappointing. Many physicists and mathematicians like to think that the
universe’s structure is simple and that simplicity rather than baroque
complexity is aesthetically appealing. Regardless, that sort of value is partly
objective and partly subjective, in the Kantian respect.
After eons of natural pseudo-selections of physical and
chemical outcomes, due to the accidental arrangements that sometimes emerge,
the third miracle occurred: the arrival of the intelligent selector. When a self-aware creature understands how
the world works, considers several alternatives, favours one as ideal and tries
to achieve that ideal, we seem to have a peculiar supplement to the indifferent
shuffling of elements by various forces and circumstances. Prior to the
evolution of persons and of self-awareness, possibilities were indifferently
realized by brute undead nature, although order in the form of
causality did develop. What we add to the flow of mindless order in the universe are our preferences
for certain possible worlds and the ingenuity to actualize them. In
particular, we prefer those worlds that reflect our values; we try to achieve
what we call the good.
We can see what’s involved here by considering this miracle
in light of an interesting discussion of our cosmic insignificance, called “Do we matter in the cosmos?” The author of that article explains the
intuition that life must be meaningless, given the unimaginable vastness of
time and space, by pointing out that even if values must be subjective, significance
can be objective as in the case of information or of causal power, and compared
to what the universe contains, our ability to influence the course of cosmic
events is vanishingly-small. So a transient creature that leaves no mark on the
universe’s evolution at large might as well not have been, from the
astronomical perspective. By contrast, a godlike being, such as a member of a
Type III civilization, on Kardashev’s scale, which member would control
a galaxy’s energy rather than the energy of a whole star or the energy that
reaches its home planet, could conceivably impact the entire universe. Cosmology
would be incomplete without reference to such a godlike being that alters the
course of galaxies.
With this in mind, we can appreciate the miracle of even
Type I artificiality, including the artificiality of our modest deviations from
the indifferent, natural course of events, because a Type III civilization must
pass through the weaker stages. Thus, we may be contributing to the rise of a
godlike generation that will be cosmically significant in the sense that its
decisions will be literally consequential even from the least parochial
perspective that would recognize the major turning points in the universe’s
development. Even if our species will be extinguished before we’re able to
graduate to Type II or III status, the universe is so vast, encompassing
hundreds of billions of galaxies and untold billions of years in its total
duration, that some intelligent species somewhere and at some time will likely
acquire that godlike power, in which case we can marvel vicariously at that
miracle which likely occurs. (We can even speculate, with Nick Bostrom, that
that miracle has already happened, that the universe has already been intelligently
redesigned, and that what we perceive as nature may be only a simulation
running in that superpowerful species’ computer.) In any case, one way to express this idea of the miracle of intelligent
selection of events is to say that the miracle is of the birth of gods which
we’ve been naively worshipping for millennia, missing the point that theistic religions
have only been foreshadowing transhumanism and the rise of technoscientific
godhood, which ironically would vindicate those ancient speculations.
Even if we lay that aside and focus on intelligent
selections that are cosmically inconsequential, we’re still faced with a
virtually supernatural affront to nature. Even the most short-lived
artificiality, the weakest, most low-tech re-engineering of the wilderness or
the most humdrum action that’s meant to realize an ideal rather than to follow
animal norms has the distinction of being anti-natural.
When we act with resentment against nature’s monstrous indifference to the life
that emerges in it, we have the significance of being cosmically novel. We rebel against nature, by learning
how it works and by devising techniques for imposing extensions of ourselves, namely
our machines, cities, and cultures, onto the undying wilderness. Even should we
fail in the end to overcome nature’s onslaught, even should we succumb to the
lethality of outer space or the tragedy of our biologically-programmed death
sentences, the least consequential action that nevertheless proceeds from
intelligent disgust with the way the world is which differs from how it should
be, objectively transcends nature by being intentionally opposed to how most of
the universe operates.
This kind of existential opposition is different from an
insane person’s delusion. When the latter intends to destroy the whole world
merely by blinking hard at it, for example, we don’t credit that doomed scheme
with miraculous audacity, because the scheme is irrational. But when our opposition
proceeds from knowledge of the natural facts and when it implicitly or
consciously is meant to alter those facts according to a plan that transcends
what mindless nature alone can do, our efforts are monumental. This is because those efforts then have a
reasonable chance of succeeding, albeit perhaps vicariously or indirectly and
in the long run, but also because they target something of the essence of all
of nature. We aim to slay the cosmic dragon whenever we act not as
preprogrammed animals or physical objects, but as persons, autonomously,
intelligently, imaginatively, and with deep-seated horror for nature’s
indifference, amorality, and ominous evolution towards a state of oblivion in
which even the gods would perish.
No comments:
Post a Comment