In the Western religious myths, God spoke the world into
being. There is no god, of course, and nature is a horrifically undead phenomenon that defies complete explanation, let alone an anthropomorphic one
that downplays the world’s fundamental impersonality. No, it’s not nature in
general that has a literary origin, but only the human world since that world
begins with us as persons. As human animals we evolved by natural selection and
by other such mechanisms, but as autonomous, encultured selves, we are indeed
spoken into being—not by any extraterrestrial intelligence, but by our thoughts
which comprise an inner voice that weaves itself into a grand fiction featuring
characters that embody our ideals, with whom we’re free to identify to begin to
salvage some meaning and dignity from what would otherwise be a perfectly absurd flow of events in
the wilderness.
We are just Characters in our Life’s Story
A self is not an immaterial thing, a ghost, and to think
that what distinguishes people from animals or objects is that we have some
such spiritual body is to reify and to fall victim to a cognitive illusion. A self is really a way of organizing
thoughts. In so far as we identify with our bodies, we’re biological
entities like the other animals, but in so far as our nature is defined by our
thinking, we become morally-significant persons. What, though, is a thought? A thought is a generalization which
simplifies for some purpose, which is to say a thought is a map or a model
which manages the chaotic flux of experience by representing those parts of the
world that interest us. The main purpose of our representations of the outer world is to predict what will happen so we can control the environment rather than be helpless to the indifferent
forces and cycles and accidents of nature. We predict by generalizing across
instances, inducing patterns by transducing and neurally binding sensory
inputs, slotting experiences into conceptual boxes for memory recall so we can
implement our plans for future projections of our identity. This allows us to
respond with greater intelligence and autonomy than could those animal species that
rely on preprogrammed, as opposed to learned, responses.
We also model the inner
world, which is to say ourselves. Through introspection, however, we have no
knowledge of our brain that organizes our experience. So although we now know
of the brain’s importance to ourselves, we have difficulty personally identifying
with that squishy mass. On the contrary, even the notion of the brain seems
alien and revolting. Instead, in our daily life we who have a personal level of
identity prefer to think of ourselves as the
character that figures in the lifelong narrative we tell to ourselves. This
narrative is the overall model that organizes our private data, the confusing signals produced by the body that we sense through
introspection, interoception, memory, and other interior channels. Roughly,
our reflexes, feelings, emotions, judgments, notions, ideas, guesses, and so
forth are organized by a personalizing story we tell.
The story is what the philosopher Marya Schachtman calls a form of diachronic unity, meaning that like a sonata or a song, a story
is a holistic structure that provides meaning to the sequential parts of which
it’s made. A fragment of a song is meaningless without the temporal structure,
which is the plan for the song that stretches across time, including the
introduction, the verses, chorus, bridge and the end. That structure is defined
partly by the genre and indeed by the lyrics which likewise tell a story,
giving the song a personality. In the same way, from the raw bits of experience
we assemble a narrative that connects our memories with our hopes and
intentions, to form a satisfying, meaningful whole. The whole of that story
amounts to our personal (as opposed to our biological) identity. A self is
something like an entire movie or play with defined characters who take the
stage at different times depending on which part of the story is presently
being “read” or called for by the rest of the world. Thus, we may occupy
different perspectives or personas, according not just to what’s happening in
the outer world, but to how we make sense of the environment with our inner
narrative. The narrative assigns roles to enable us to socialize, to retain our
dignity under trying circumstances, or to perform other functions.
The story that defines us is still being written while we’re
alive, and we identify with different characters in different contexts. The
meaning of each character, though, is given by the entire script. The script is
composed of the inner voice that continually speaks its interpretations and
organizes experience to preserve what the existential anthropologist Ernest
Becker would call our “self-esteem.” Becker showed how the self is formed
psychologically and socially as a defense against the angst suffered by every
child who learns that the world doesn’t serve his or her whims. We tap into
cultural reservoirs of meaning, or “hero-systems,” to preserve the self-esteem
that acts as a buffer against anxiety. Similarly, Yuval Harari points to the
collective fictions that sustain civilization, allowing the members to avoid
conflict by defining themselves nationalistically, according to myths that
justify the social power distributions. Both of these aspects of our
existential story are relevant, as we’ll see, but the more immediate source of
selfhood is the narrative that occupies our thoughts.
The narrative that distinguishes our inner voice, which
artists excel at expressing in concrete outward forms, emerges as we choose at
each moment how to interpret a particular experience. The personal pattern
forms after certain types of interpretations accrue, because they support our
pride or esteem. There is, though, no homunculus which reads or writes the
story. The script writes itself as a
result of the conflict between our clever animality and the indifference of the
outer world which threatens all such creatures with anxiety that can be
alleviated only by suicide or by resort to the magic of art. We create ourselves for the same reason we
create the outer artificial worlds, because awakened beings require a
refuge from the horrific wilderness. Where we are presently in the
story, that is, the bookmarked page, as it were, is determined by the limits of
the character we occupy at a particular time that has more or less
understanding of the total story in which that character plays its part.
Ultimately, we’re equal to the characters whose thoughts and actions are defined
and contextualized by a series of meta-thoughts, by a narrative that provides
our whole life with existential meaning.
Fictional Selves and Literary Morality
The philosopher Galen Strawson points out, however, that not everyone explicitly narrates their life. Strawson quotes from
famous individuals who confess their memory is too poor to figure in worthy
inner narratives; instead, they experience themselves as a confused series of
experiences. If they take to writing their biography, as in the case of
Montaigne, they do so objectively, drawing no distinction between the inner and
outer worlds and thus modeling themselves, at best, for the sake of greater
prediction and control, having no aesthetic end in view. Moreover, he says, in
line with Becker and Harari, some such narrations may be traps that render
ourselves inauthentic, as we adopt conventions that are only socially
convenient. Instead of demonstrating finesse in creating our personal, existentially-noble
self by gradually telling our story via introspection and meta-reflection, we
may resort to clichés such as stock characters so that we play out only the
roles that society assigns us. All of which seems correct, but contrary to
Strawson, this doesn’t falsify the foregoing account of the self; instead, the
account has unsettling, but non-disqualifying implications.
One of those implications is that there are degrees of personhood. Some biological
humans are more personal than others. A character can be more or less
distinguished, more or less the result of inward reflections and visionary
projections of meaning which are the marks of superior artistry. Crucially,
introverts are more personal than extroverts. This is to say that
each of us attains greater personhood to the extent that we engage in
introspection and meta-reflection. To the extent we’re focused only on acting,
not on thinking about ourselves, we lose our self. In that case, we should be
identified only with our biological humanity and with the roles we play as
defined by the stories that others
tell about us to organize us as objects of their
models. If we haven’t thought about the meaning of our life’s stages, about
what sort of story we’re living out, we have no right to speak of us as being
authentic, self-made (spontaneously and privately-generated) persons. The word
“person,” then, is an honourific title ascribed to someone who performs well at
certain cognitive tasks.
Second, if someone engages in no inner modeling at all,
she’ll have no self-understanding. She’ll have failed to know herself, that
being the task sufficing to create a worthy self in the first place. Suppose,
for example, you have no interest in inner narration, but you do reflect on
your experience in the same way that you organize your encounters with the
outer world. In that case, you do model your thoughts and feelings, but you
objectify yourself; that is, you treat
yourself as just another object: you generalize over your inner contents for
greater predictive power and instrumental control. You take a pragmatic, impersonal attitude toward yourself
rather than distinguishing your character in moral or in aesthetic terms.
Still, you’ll understand yourself at some level; indeed, you may have greater
self-control than the enchanted inner narrator. But if you don’t interpret your
thoughts and feelings at all, not even to objectify them, your stream of inner
experience must be quite animal-like. You may suffer from autism or from some
other antisocial personality disorder, which renders you more like a robot than
a person.
There are, then, two sources of meta-reflection, the private
and the public. Private reflection is the stuff of introversion, of segregating yourself from society to question
conventions in deep, philosophical investigations of what’s really happening. By
contrast, culture is the product of
collective reflection, and we tend to defer to culture in our moments of
extroversion, when we’re absorbed with some activity or when our self-esteem is
sustained by diversions that require others’ participation. Thus,
interpretations and character roles can be narrated privately or publicly, and
the typical self (that is, the human way of organizing thoughts) is a mixture
of idiosyncrasies and artistic leaps of imagination, on the one hand, and
politically-useful frauds, on the other. The
more introverted we are, the more liable we’re to engage in subversive
meta-reflection, and so the more the meaning of our inner narrative will depend
on the latter’s opposition to the prevailing
culture. By contrast, the more
extroverted we are, the more we immerse ourselves in the ruling myths that bind
the masses, that provide excuses for the power inequalities which are almost
always objectively grotesque. In the latter case, our defining story may be
bereft of existential authenticity or nobility. Think of Willy Loman from Death of a Salesman. If the extrovert
only defers to cultural codes of conduct, without pondering them, being always lost
in some business or other that leaves no time for meta-reflection or for the
development of an inner voice that tells her life’s story to herself, she can
hardly be called a person in the morally-significant sense. Her activities will
be only implicitly meaningful, because the story that defines her will be told only
in cultural forums such as churches, movie theaters, clubs, or political
conventions.
A third implication is that the morality that suits the
nature of a self is wholly aesthetic.
A self is just a work of art, produced mainly by cognitive mechanisms. We’re
not born people, but must earn that title by thinking hard about what we are
and what we should be in relation to the outer world as it really is and as we
transform it. A self is the narrative structure that supplies the meaning of
the characters we play at different stages of our journey. This meaning is
ultimately the same found in any fiction.
A story either excels in creative, artistic terms or it fails to delight or to
inspire. Likewise, a person’s virtues or vices make sense only as efforts to
live up to a literary ideal in the broadest sense. The relevant kind of story
isn’t that which is written in book form, but it is linguistic, because words
are likely key to conceptual binding and thus to the mind’s modeling functions.
We become people, who are subjects that have dignity according to certain
stories, only when we acquire a special way of organizing our thoughts as
opposed to letting them flow with no autonomous control or understanding of
them. We organize our mental contents by interpreting them in light of a
cognitive map or model that takes the form of a narrative. All of these
life-sustaining narratives are fictions,
because they’re only simplifications rather than reproductions of what is
modeled. (Even scientific theories, then, are fictions in that they idealize in their inevitable simplifications. They include ceteris paribus rules that presuppose an exclusion of much of the world, for practical purposes of inquiry. These theories are nonfictional only in the institutional sense, because they're intended not to entertain but to discover some empirical truth. Institutional fictions, such as novels or movies may also represent some empirical truth, but they're produced with different intentions.) Nevertheless, they’re fictions that have real impacts on the world, preventing an epidemic of suicide and driving us to achieve
our guiding ideals.
A person is morally valuable, then, just in so far as she’s
a literary object, a character whose greatness depends on the quality of the
tale that captures the creative meaning of her life’s work and journey. You
often hear an attempt to capture this tale in the eulogy offered by the
relatives of a recently-deceased individual. The essence of a great life is the
originality displayed in the struggle to overcome the existential absurdity
which would otherwise entail suicide. But a great individual overcomes also the
banality and instrumentality of the social myths that lend meaning to a life at
the cost of turning the individual into a beta, into a follower who in carrying
out her functions indirectly acts as a pawn in the scheme of some greater, more
distinguished individual. Most so-called people
are only barely personal beings, because their existential efforts are mediocre.
They don’t struggle to exist as
transcendent creatures, as human animals who acquire personality by
accumulating the cognitive habit of interpreting their inner data according to
a dawning vision of what a self should be; they don’t wrestle with the meaning
of their life or with what sort of person they’ve become.
On the contrary, moral value has generally been construed as
being non-aesthetic, on the assumption that the self exists without the need
for much human effort. The self is presumed to be either a spirit created by
God or a sort of rational agency that has natural rights. There’s been much
talk, therefore, of moral laws as befitting the objectivity of personhood. On
the foregoing account, though, an individual’s moral value is fittingly
subjective, because we’re speaking of subjects that transcend the objective
world, that resist its absurdity with titanic acts of artistic will and vision.
We think ourselves into higher being by
writing the stories that animate us in our daily activities. The writing
occurs in the narrations of our inner voice, which may or may not set the
details of the story down as an autobiography, and in the publicly-available
myths that serve political (civilizational) purposes as well as existential
(artistic) ones.
Very beautiful essay, I've always enjoyed your take on the moral life as being primarily aesthetic and this was a pleasing restatement. I especially like the analogy of the book.
ReplyDelete2 essays in a week, to what do we owe the bounty?
Hi, Guthrie. The Millennials article is pretty short, and I wrote it a few weeks ago, submitting it to Salon, but never heard back from them so I posted it here. It's tough finding an online magazine that's interested in my kind of writing.
DeleteIt's interesting that there is this view in cognitive science, which identifies the self as literally a sort of narrative. This view fits nicely with the Nietzschean aesthetic take on morality. So I put them together in this article. I think the narrative view fits also with the higher-order-thought theory of consciousness, which I've also presented on this blog.
Next up is likely a dialogue on social justice warriors.
Your interpretation of the self as narration is very much in line with recent neurological findings and Buddhisms concept of non/not-self, that there is no core part of us but rather the self is an emergent phenomena arising from the interdependent impermenant interactions between internal components with the external, like memory, constantly being reassembled and reconstructed.
ReplyDeleteThe issue I see though is how is existential aesthetic rebellion and dignity possible when not only our self is ephereal and transient, removing the will part pf free will, but bound and written by our biology. As various studies into genetics have shown, such as with separated twins, our personalities appear heavily based in our biologu and formed very early in our lives, social conditioning snd instincts locking in whatever mold is allowed by our genes in early childhood. So, even in introspection, we're not really writing any unoaue story, as our self is already formed beyond our perception, and any change that occurs in it seems to stem from external social influence and circumstance.
Furthermore, are not our standards for what is aesthetically heroic or dignified also alrgely defined by or against the greater social narratoves and archtypes?
I can see how the above non-essentialist account of the self might be consistent with the Buddhist view that the folk, egoistic presumptions about the self are based on illusions. I have some differences with Buddhism and Daoism, as I've explained in other articles (links below).
DeleteThe relevant question here is whether the self is so inessential and unreal that there's nothing there worth holding onto, so that our goal should be to learn to accept that the self is as good as nothing. Moksha would then be liberation from the illusion that the self exists as any sort of independent entity, and from the craving for everlasting life, which causes suffering. I'd disagree with Buddhists there. The "fiction" of the self is an emergent property, a character whose meaning is dependent on a story we tell ourselves to make sense of our experience, and that character has real causal impact on the inner and outer worlds.
Which brings us to the issue of freewill. You raise some good questions. Have you had a look at the dialogue I wrote on freewill? (See the link below.) Roughly, the point I'd make is that if our genes and the environment (our upbringing, etc) can have impacts on our character, choices, and actions, then so can our higher self, so the question is only about the _degree_ of our self-control (autonomy, freewill). That higher self consists of the cerebral cortex and the higher-order (or meta) thoughts, which come to the fore in moments of introspection and introversion, which can alter our self-model, as opposed to being epiphenomenal. That inner growth or self-directed transformation can happen in therapy or after taking psychedelic, life-altering substances, for example. We can modify our character and our behaviour if we reflect hard enough and come to terms with whether we've done enough to live up to our ideals.
I agree, though, that we shouldn't be so proud of ourselves, no matter what we do, because if we do have freewill, it is indeed narrow. We don't want to be like Donald Trump, who thinks he's the greatest businessman in the world, who thus has to lie to himself and to others about all the advantages he had in life for which he can take no credit. The proper attitude for an authentic, truly self-made person is based on humility and on an insistence on honour (coming to terms with harsh reality, including the extent to which we are indeed often puppets). We shouldn't boast, as if we have an immaterial core (a so-called soul or spirit) which has absolute control over our biological side, as if a homosexual person, for example, could will himself to overcome his hormones.
http://rantswithintheundeadgod.blogspot.ca/2015/05/clash-of-worldviews-free-will-edition.html
http://rantswithintheundeadgod.blogspot.ca/2011/11/buddhism-and-existential-angst.html
http://rantswithintheundeadgod.blogspot.ca/2013/08/daoist-pantheism-natures-tragedy-and.html