The suspension of disbelief in fictions has become
paradoxical. We find we must ignore our doubts to entertain ourselves not just
when we’re reading novels or watching movies, but when we engage with ideology
or adhere to the narrative we’re constantly telling ourselves to dignify our
life with purpose. In prehistoric times, there was no need to suspend disbelief
in the telling of myths, because facts weren’t divorced from values and so
there was no such thing generally as the kind of hyper-rational skepticism that
can spoil a narrative. For the opposite reason, in what we call the modern Age
of Reason, taking fiction seriously is likewise almost impossible: the
science-centered doubts become overbearing, we become cynical and nihilistic,
and yet most of us choose to act as though the myths still matter.
Fact, Value, and the Mythopoeic Dreamworld
The poet Samuel Taylor Coleridge coined the phrase “willing
suspension of disbelief,” when he defended his reference to supernatural
elements in his poetry even in the nineteenth century at which time educated
readers were taken with the science-centered, naturalistic view of the world.
Coleridge said that not only could an author “transfer from our inward nature a
human interest and a semblance of truth sufficient to procure for these shadows
of imagination that willing suspension of disbelief for the moment, which
constitutes poetic faith,” but the reverse could be achieved, “to give the
charm of novelty to things of every day, and to excite a feeling analogous to
the supernatural, by awakening the mind's attention from the lethargy of
custom, and directing it to the loveliness and the wonders of the world before
us” (Biographia Literaria). In other words, if a reader can be led to identify
with the story’s characters and offered enough verisimilitude in the details,
the reader could overlook the story’s unreality for the sake of enjoying the
experience of reading the narrative. Moreover, in the case of Romanticism, magical
realism or some such genre, a reader can be shown that the so-called mundane,
material reality of everyday objects belies a strangeness which we’re no longer
predisposed to perceive. For Coleridge and Wordsworth, who co-wrote the poems
that prompted Coleridge’s coining of the phrase, poetry thus could address
science’s disenchantment of the world, that is, the rise of skepticism and
objectivity which had severed fact from value in our understanding of our
experience. Either the supernatural could be portrayed as normal and realistic
or nature could be presented as bizarre and magical. Either way, poetry and art
in general could rejoin fact and value.
The quality of life
for humans in the Paleolithic Age was likely mythopoeic, meaning that
the prehistoric hunter-gatherers didn’t perceive facts as being separable from
values. This isn’t to say they had no accurate beliefs, since they could
hardly have survived a day in the teeming wilderness if none of their concepts had
been practical or attuned to nature. Indeed, if they personified natural
processes in their animistic dramatizations, that supernaturalism may itself
have been crucial to their survival. An objective understanding of nature’s
impersonality had better wait for an epoch in which the population has the
technoscientific control to reassure itself with luxuries, just as an adult’s
jadedness isn’t fit for a child. Had the hunter-gatherers been forced to conceive
of nature as having no redemptive purpose or moral value, the savagery and carnage
all around them in the wild would likely have overwhelmed them and driven them
to suicide or madness. Only a society that’s equipped itself with a buffer of
protective artificiality could indulge in skeptical meditations on the world’s
godlessness and on its ultimate indifference to all creatures. Without cities
and civilizations, and supported only by small bands of kith and kin who stood
against predators, diseases, and natural disasters, Paleolithic humans could at
least fall back on their mental armor, as it were, on their naïve, comforting
humanization of alien reality, that is, on their projecting of social
categories onto inhuman forces and mechanisms.
In any case, the animists would have conceived of natural facts
as having implicit value. “Perhaps the rock or the wind is possessed by a
spirit,” they surmised. And conversely, values were conceived of as having
objective reality, as opposed to being illusory or epiphenomenal. You could
cast a spell and your intentions would infuse with a magical procedure, which
would result in some objectively meaningful, real event. If the spell didn’t
work as expected, that was no cause for alarm, because a natural state of
affairs was as ambiguous as a person’s mental state, given the comingling of
facts and values. You could interpret someone’s apparent anger differently,
depending on the background concepts you brought to bear, taking into account
more or less of the person’s recent history. Likewise, if all physical events
have personal meanings due to their relation to a supernatural society of
spirits, you could evaluate them in many ways, depending on how well you
understand the spirits’ intentions.
The fusion of fact and
value has a basis in cognitive science, in the evidence for something like a
Kantian view of perception as opposed to a strictly empirical, stimulus-driven
one. See, for example, Helmholtz’s theory of how sensations
aren’t copied onto nerve endings, but are encoded as signs which themselves
have learned properties which figure in the “unconscious inferences” we employ
in making sense of what we perceive. Cognitive scientist Anil Seth explains that for Helmholtz, perception is “a process of inference, in which
indeterminate sensory signals are combined with prior expectations or ‘beliefs’
about the way the world is, to form the brain’s optimal hypotheses of the
causes of these sensory signals—of coffee cups, computers and clouds. What we
see is the brain’s ‘best guess’ of what’s out there.” The brain is a
“prediction machine,” and the a priori
element is the creativity of conceiving of hypotheses to test against the
empirical data. According to this view of “predictive processing,” writes Seth,
“perception is a controlled hallucination,
in which the brain’s hypotheses are continually reined in by sensory signals
arriving from the world and the body.” The reason perception is hallucinatory
or partly subjective is that it’s full of meaning, as informed by the
organizing “signs” (concepts) that embody our a priori guesses or expectations, and that meaning doesn’t exist in
the stimulus (the external cause of experience).
The attempt to understand the world begins, then, with play,
when the child freely associates this with that, including subjects with
objects, extending what the philosopher Dan Dennett calls the intentional
stance (our expectation that creatures like us have minds whose beliefs and
desires we can interpret so we can better predict their behaviour). Prior to
its accumulation of much experience, the brain’s initial thinking proceeds
along the lines of a dream so that the person’s waking state resembles her
unconscious processing. That is, the conscious ego, distinct from everything
else, hasn’t yet emerged in the child’s mind. Only after sufficient testing of
hypotheses against patterns of sensations, after the child forms a reliable
mental model, capable of explaining a wide range of phenomena will the child
realize she can examine her model at a meta level and engage in detached,
philosophical reflections or even experiments. The historical analogue of child’s
play is our distant animistic past, at which time there had not yet been many
deep discoveries of how the real world works. Only after the intellectual and
technological progress that we associate with history, beginning around 12,000
years ago, could we have arrived at a culture that takes for granted the
unreality or illusoriness of play and subjectivity, of magic and the
supernatural. Only after sufficient
historical, collective testing of expectations
could we have built up a collective mental map that allows parents to pass
onto their children insights and discoveries that were millennia in the making.
The formation of concepts that organize our perception of
the world can be likened to the painting of a picture that begins with the
portrayal of chaos, chaos being like the unconscious, dreamlike play with cognitive
possibilities. A digital artist, for example, can combine photographic
references, randomly or intuitively turning and distorting them, playing with
the transparencies to challenge her unconscious faculties to detect patterns.
She may have no idea what she wants to paint until she’s inspired by some shape
or colour she happens to see in the jumble on her canvas. That moment of
conceptual clarity is like the act of unconscious hypothesizing. “I know what
this chaos wants to be,” she may say to herself. “I can paint a tiger out of
these suggestive blobs.” She then accentuates and develops the tiger-like parts
of the image. It’s the same with sculpture, when the sculptor examines a large
block of stone or wood, imagining what organized whole could be carved from the
inchoate forms. A musician such as Trent Reznor can likewise begin by recording
noises and listening for hints of sonic order, which he then focuses on and
refines (or which he sends to Atticus Ross to handle the refinement). A
novelist may seek inspiration for story ideas by randomly combining words drawn
from the dictionary or from other texts.
The point is that both
the individual brain and the early stage of our collective mental development
likewise begin with overflowing unconscious energy, with a flurry of creative
hypotheses to prevent us from prejudging the environment or dooming us to be
wholly unprepared to survive. If a bird finds itself underwater, it will
have no way to adapt because its body-type specializes in flying not swimming. The
bird is locked into that way of life and is helpless in other environments. Our
greatest advantage is our mental flexibility, which begins with that childlike
wonder for possibilities in an unconscious dream world. If a creature with our
relatively defenseless phenotype came with hardwired prejudices or preferences
for dealing with only a narrow range of situations, we wouldn’t have learned
the weaknesses or our competitors or been able to adapt to life on the land or in
the air or sea, and in hot and cold climates. Only because our mental growth
begins with the free association of ideas—which occurs not just in our
individual childhood but in psychedelic experience and in our nightly dreams—have
we been able to infer reliable models of natural patterns, after disposing of
so many duds throughout history.
The Paradox of Modern Faith in Myths
Notice, then, that the animists wouldn’t have been able to
suspend their realistic doubts, because they had no such doubts in the first
place or at least none that were culturally established (since of course there
were ancient skeptics here and there). Likewise, to say that, on average,
children in any historical period suspend their disbelief, to allow themselves
to be entertained by a fictional story, would involve a misuse of the phrase.
You don’t have to ask a child twice for her to entertain even the most
ludicrous fantasy. Eventually, at around six years of age, a child may begin to
suspect that you’re only joking if you tell her one whopper after another. Moreover,
modern children aren’t exactly animists, because the prevailing pragmatic and
materialistic notions creep into all levels of our discourse. But children are generally eager to play and
to “make-believe,” because children are imaginative as well as credulous.
Children are trusting for evolutionary reasons, so they can absorb their
parents’ lessons to fuel their mighty brain and to overcome the relative helplessness
of the rest of their body. Their rudimentary notion of how the facts diverge
from the world they imagine or prefer will still be laden with value, since
teaching a child the true cosmicist horror of nature’s absolute indifference to
life would amount to abuse. When Mother tells her daughter that nothing can be
done about the rain that falls on her birthday, the child may harbor resentment as if someone somewhere were still to blame, because she doesn’t understand the
brute physicality of natural cause and effect. In any case, children express
their free-flowing imagination to maximize the situations to which they can
adapt as they mature, and the same was true for our prehistoric period of
collective mental development.
Two further questions arise about the suspension of
disbelief. First, how do we modern ideologues, including monotheists,
nationalists, and humanistic fans of technoscientific progress maintain our
faith in our mass fictions? Now that history has reached what Nietzsche called
the twilight of the idols, after the Scientific Revolution has established the
world’s fundamental amorality and pointlessness, and the Industrial Revolution
has even adjusted us to the metaphysics of materialism by training the masses
to act like robots (functionaries), what mechanisms must be in place to
preserve the imagination and the myths needed for civilized cooperation? The
dystopian film Brazil explored this
problem by contrasting an inhuman bureaucracy with an individual’s quests for
personal freedom and romantic love. The protagonist Sam Lowry’s dreams erupt
with fantasies of his heroism in finding the perfect woman and in joining a
rebellion against the oppressive regime. Unlike the functionaries who busy
themselves with drudgework, Sam not only suspends his disbelief in those dreams,
but overcompensates by obsessing over his unconscious musings. He effectively
joins the “terroristic” resistance and abuses his power to protect his newfound
romantic partner, but the totalitarian system triumphs, capturing and torturing
Sam until he takes refuge in a blissful coma. He divorces himself from harsh
reality, preferring his humanitarian fantasy.
This film deals with
extremes to clarify our situation, which is that the world of facts is absurd
in itself, and adding values to that world makes for a double absurdity. Of
course, we add moral and aesthetic values precisely to overcome absurdity,
especially when we imagine that the world can be made meaningful if only we
apply our ideals by technologically undoing the natural wilderness. But the underlying existential absurdity
persists in the paradox of our having to sustain faith in our myths even when
we know or ought to know that myths are only subjectively meaningful and that
the objective world has no purpose or redeeming qualities. The real universe
will of course eventually swallow up all living things, and it will be as if no
spellbinding tales had ever been told or heroic deeds been performed. Some of
the cognitive and social mechanisms of suspending disbelief in fictions are
readily understood, as I’ve explained elsewhere. For example, we need a unifying fiction to overlook our natural differences and
to allow us to cooperate for the collective good. Thus we have not just
theological, but political, economic, and infotainment myths which keep us on
the same page, as it were; we identify with our culturally-established roles
instead of all behaving like boorish egotists. The more we dwell on the existential facts, the more we’re inclined to
see through ideologies as the utilitarian fictions they are, which
enlightenment turns us into criminals or outcasts. (This is the sort of
problem Dostoevsky took up in some of his novels, for example.) So if only to remain secure within
civilized society, we must defer to conventional wisdom. At the same time, the more firmly
scientific naturalism establishes itself, the greater the cognitive dissonance
for anyone seeking comfort from a myth.
For example, how do modern Christians believe that a man two
thousand years ago rose from the dead and ascended to Heaven so that the rest
of us could join him forever with the personal creator of the universe? Liberal
Christians who respect the power of science are inclined to treat the Christian
creed as entirely metaphorical, in which case their religion is effectively the
same as organized enthusiasm for the aesthetic merit of any other great work of
fiction. However, this sort of Christian is unlikely to be as zealous as, say,
a fan at Comic-Con, because the Christian myth doesn’t speak to real-world
concerns in our century; crucially, the Christian fiction isn’t science-fictional, so its metaphors
won’t resonate compared to the secular myths. Thus, liberal Christians can’t
dedicate their life to obsessing over the minutia of Christian theology the way
Star Wars inspires a grown man to dress up as Chewbacca while waiting in line
for a movie ticket or the way Sam Lowry’s fantasies overwhelm his mundane
obligations.
By contrast, conservative Christians will trust in their
myth’s literal truth, at the cost of failing to understand the mountains of
literal truth supplied by science and philosophy; alternatively, the myth’s
epistemic status will be bastardized by the science-centered notion of mere
literal truth, and so the conservative will be left with neither rationality
nor faith. Either way, cognitive dissonance is minimized, because in the liberal
case the myth’s power to enchant is undone by a prior commitment to
rationality, and in the conservative case the myth possesses the believer,
making her an anachronism or else her faith becomes vulgar, thanks to her
failure to appreciate that profane myths rule modern societies. In neither case
is disbelief suspended with much benefit, and so nature’s absurdity bubbles up
through the floorboards. Kierkegaard tried to drive home the point that
Christian faith should be absurd
rather than rationalized, but he’s an exception to the kind of “Christian” who
prevails in Christendom.
Or take the secular myth that capitalism maximizes welfare,
that individual selfishness can be harnessed to everyone’s mutual advantage in
that society. Again, the capitalist ideal is never fully actualized because the
ideal is counterfactual. Thus, while competition does create innovation, it
also creates blowback in the form of the resentful colonized masses that the
upper class inevitably exploits to maximize their profits and preserve their
ill-gotten wealth. Their wealth is always unearned in practice, because
deregulation allows the wealthy to game the system, to capture the watchdogs
and the politicians with lobbyists so as to slip through loopholes,
externalizing or hiding the costs of their business and effectively defrauding
the public. The American financial system, for example, disguises its true
nature with obscure language and bogus mathematical models. Nevertheless, the myth of capitalism
justifies the amorality of the public sphere and the grotesque economic
inequalities between classes and nations, because we manage somehow to at least
partially suspend our disbelief. This is proven by the fact that revolts
against capitalism are abnormal, at least in North America, whereas private morality or good taste would
mandate that we search for a more humane way of doing business. How, then, do
we ignore the reality of capitalism? How do we buy into the American promise of
liberty and happiness, that is, the liberty to sin and the addicting pleasure
of dining on horrific McDonald’s hamburgers which make you sick and obese,
eventually depriving you of that same liberty? How do we entertain the secular
ideology even when we know it’s just a story?
A large part of the answer—besides the facts that
civilization seems better than anarchy, as is any delusion to constant
anxiety—is that we’re easily distracted,
as is demonstrated by the industry of magic tricks. Just as children are
innately trusting, adults evidently have cognitive blind spots which may
naturally accommodate the Law of Oligarchy. To help justify the dominance
hierarchies that inevitably form in social groups of animals, we must have
evolved tendencies to submit to authorities, to adjust our expectations of
happiness to our social station, or, if we should win the lottery and find
ourselves with oligarchic privileges, to fulfill the archetype of the mad king,
unlearning our conscience and spitting on slave morality. Thus, when the mass
media present us with scandals, soap operas, and sordid daily news of murders,
atrocities, and disasters, we go with the flow instead of detaching from the
system to ask the urgent meta-questions. We
allow the cultural magic trick to unfold as a price we pay for civilized life.
The cost isn’t immediate, because the distractions are always entertaining, but
an effect of submitting to such noise is that we become drudges. Existential
authenticity and creativity require that we confront absurd reality instead of
losing ourselves in the mass media patter. Of course, these distractions also assist
the modern megamachine which is responsible for untold ecological damages.
The second question is just how we suspend disbelief in our private fiction which constitutes our
spirit or consciousness, that is, the higher-order thoughts of our narrative self. In our introverted moments, we consciously
absorb events by interpreting them in light of our overarching story, the one
that consists of our thoughts about our memories, character, friends, family, enemies,
possessions, hobbies, occupation, and so on. We play starring roles in our
master tale, in our private metanarrative which lends subjective meaning to
everything we do and everything that happens to us. This private myth acts like
a filter, and any experience that isn’t readily assimilated by the myth’s
assumptions will either not be understood at all or else it will be excluded as
foreign, whereupon the thought of it will fester until the unconscious eventually
makes sense of it to maintain our self-esteem and to prevent the pains of
further cognitive dissonance.
Again, the question is whether these cognitive mechanisms
can endure the twilight of the idols. Can we continue to believe in ourselves,
knowing now that we aren’t immaterial substances, but are just characters made
up of a series of deep thoughts that comprise our self-serving life’s story?
We’re immortal only in so far as our tales can outlive us if our story impacts
the tales that others tell. Our immortality thus piggybacks on the external
forms of language, especially on the written word which can last for millennia.
How, though, can we suspend not just our
disbelief but our horror, knowing that the most prized part of our personal
self can be nothing more than some such disappointment, some mere tall tale?
How can we trust in our character and in our inner narrative, knowing that its
author and primary audience are one, that our meaning is aesthetic and thus
largely subjective, that most personal stories are dismal and clichéd, and
that, quite contrary to the philosopher Derrida, there is indeed something
outside the text, namely the real world which ultimately makes a mockery of all
our interpretations?
Perhaps part of the answer is that by believing in
ourselves, which means believing in the story we’re constantly telling
ourselves, we enjoy the thrill of being actors in starring roles. Actors tend
to be narcissists because when they’re on stage or being filmed they’re at the
center of many people’s attention. In so far as we act in different roles,
depending on which part of our personality is called upon to handle some
situation, we act as if we were professional actors. YouTube and celebrity
culture only exacerbate the thrill of being stars in our life’s story. Even
when no one else is watching or when no one else will know what we’re doing, we always consciously or unconsciously observe
our actions. We may be proud or ashamed of ourselves, but as long as we
contextualize our choices and behaviour according to our master narrative, we have
at least an implicit audience, namely the potential for our meta-thoughts to
interpret our first-order experience. Even a starving homeless person can fall
back on the feeling that he’s performing
his life, that he’s always the center of someone’s attention, and that
although he hardly enjoys a movie star’s fame or accolades, he nevertheless
succeeds in acting out his assigned role. By occupying this street corner
rather than that one, he makes a creative choice as determined by the inner
script that provides meaning to his life; without any such meaning, his life
would be intolerable. Yet there he endures, day after day, disheveled and
piss-stained as he is. Why does even such a lowly figure carry on believing in
himself when most people would hurl his inner script into the flames? For most
of us, the show must go on and so we perform for the aesthetic glory of acting
in the spotlight, if only for the brief time we’re allotted in our episode.
No comments:
Post a Comment