The
existential philosopher Heidegger distinguished between traditional and modern,
or roughly between low and high, technologies. The former, such as windmills or hand-sewn clothing,
work with nature and have aesthetic appeal as quasi-artworks, whereas the
latter, such as computers or nuclear power plants, challenge the sovereignty of external forces,
by storing energy to be used at our discretion. Scientific modes of thinking
prepare the way for modern technology by abstracting from the individuality of
everything in nature, from what Heidegger called their “thinghood”,
objectifying and dissecting (analyzing) natural phenomena and thus encouraging
us to adopt an instrumental, Machiavellian attitude towards them.
When we appreciate something’s uniqueness, we’re more likely to personalize it, since people tend to be especially different from each other: our brains have different experiences over time and there are practically endless ways for our neurons to store that information, by forming unique interconnections. Thus, early forms of religion are animistic, anthropomorphizing the natural world on the basis of the perceived uniqueness shared by the likes of rivers, trees, or mountains, on the one hand, and humans on the other. Modernists would say that the ancients thereby lacked our depth of understanding of nature. The metaphor of standing under something is actually less apt than that of standing apart from it. Modern scientists gain perspective by emotionally detaching from what they studied, thus withholding their sympathy. They employ mathematics and other abstract modes of thinking to engage in extreme forms of generalization, or “unification,” treating rivers, trees, and mountains, for example, all as masses in motion. When things appear to lose their individuality, our sympathetic reflexes are no longer triggered, because we don’t feel compelled to personify them and thus we don’t extend to them anything like human rights. We thereby take up a nihilistic stance towards the objectified phenomena, using technology to overpower nature instead of incorporating nature's organic rhythms into our lifestyle.
When we appreciate something’s uniqueness, we’re more likely to personalize it, since people tend to be especially different from each other: our brains have different experiences over time and there are practically endless ways for our neurons to store that information, by forming unique interconnections. Thus, early forms of religion are animistic, anthropomorphizing the natural world on the basis of the perceived uniqueness shared by the likes of rivers, trees, or mountains, on the one hand, and humans on the other. Modernists would say that the ancients thereby lacked our depth of understanding of nature. The metaphor of standing under something is actually less apt than that of standing apart from it. Modern scientists gain perspective by emotionally detaching from what they studied, thus withholding their sympathy. They employ mathematics and other abstract modes of thinking to engage in extreme forms of generalization, or “unification,” treating rivers, trees, and mountains, for example, all as masses in motion. When things appear to lose their individuality, our sympathetic reflexes are no longer triggered, because we don’t feel compelled to personify them and thus we don’t extend to them anything like human rights. We thereby take up a nihilistic stance towards the objectified phenomena, using technology to overpower nature instead of incorporating nature's organic rhythms into our lifestyle.
Technology
Humanizes Nature
This
Heideggerian criticism of technology is compelling but it doesn’t go far
enough, in my view. There’s a deeper process at work in the use of all
technologies, motivated by a more general way of thinking than just scientific
objectification. Our tendency to personify is rooted simply in our inevitable
resort to metaphors. When we
categorize, we group things and think of them as instances of a type, thus
comparing them to each other, perhaps anchoring the comparison to a simplified
mental representation (a stereotype or exemplar). Our most fundamental
analogies extend our common and familiar experiences--seeing, walking, eating,
learning, dying, and so on--to less well-known phenomena. That extension of
human experience in our confrontation with the nonhuman is the primary act of
anthropomorphism, which means that virtually all of our thoughts are
fundamentally anthropomorphic. If you look at the historical basis of most of
our concepts, you’ll find a generalization based on an analogy between some
quaint human experience and something less familiar and thus apparently
nonhuman, that is, some broader natural phenomenon like a rainstorm or a
stellar configuration.
Our
great felicity with categories goes together with our use of even the humblest
technologies, including those that Heidegger would praise for working with
rather than against nature. All technologies import aspects of us to nonhuman
phenomena, just as even our most primitive cognitive act, our use of metaphors,
tames the unfamiliar by comparing it with everyday human experience. When we
build even the simplest device, like an axe or a hut, we transform the nonhuman
world and render it less forbidding and alien. As the biologist Richard
Dawkins or the communications theorist Marshall McLuhan would say, we extend
our phenotypes, meaning our bodies. But this isn’t just because we supply a
car, for example, with a front that looks like a human face or because a gun or
a camera improves on a particular body part such as the fist or the eye. The
extension common to all technologies is that of our brain’s innate body plan,
as pictured in the so-called cortical homunculus, with which we map out and instinctively
identify most strongly with our body parts, regarding anything not so mapped as
foreign, hostile, or disgusting. Thus, we don’t retreat even from our foulest body
odours--or from those of people with whom we form strong emotional bonds--as
reflexively as we do from those of strangers. We render the wilderness less
terrifyingly strange just by leaving our footprint in it, as it were, reshaping
nature somehow according to our designs so that, like proud children just
released from arts and crafts class, we can hold up our pet project and say,
“Look what I made!” At least if we have a hand in making something, we’re faced
with the devil we know.
Existential
Cosmicism and our Masks and Mirrors
By
contrast, we create our human identity at an early age when we learn to draw
that Cartesian distinction between mind and material world. We appreciate that
we’re born into a pre-existing, nonhuman world that’s often hostile and peculiarly
indifferent to our plight, and we cope by humanizing that world, populating it
with ghosts, goblins, and gods from our imagination, shamelessly projecting
images of us onto natural forces as though we were in any sense central to the
cosmos. The cosmicist insists that our horrifying and tragic absurdity consists
in our peripheral metaphysical status, in the abyss between our self-image as
VIPs and our natural identity as practically trapped and cursed parasites,
feasting on our monstrous host which is the undead god, the mindlessly evolving and thus creative plenum that scientists call
nature. Our explosion of technology is the outward manifestation of that inner,
cognitive revolution: our minds explode with concepts, analogies, and
projections, as we mentally dress the world in human clothes, as it were, to
mask its dreadful inhumaneness and revolting monstrosity, and our busy hands
put that frantic mental activity to work, turning our mere ghostlike ideas into
tangible transformations of the environment.
Horrified
by the complement of our vainglorious sentience, of our original sin of playing
up the difference between us and the rest of the world, we rush to rectify our resulting
alienation. We reduce nature’s strangeness by those inner technologies, if you
like, by our mental representations which depend on anthropomorphic metaphors,
but also by outer, body-built technologies which physically humanize the
bizarre outgrowths on nature’s decaying corpse. For example, we don’t just let
waterfalls fall, but need to get the last word in, turning them into power
sources or tourist attractions; nor do we passively watch the sun’s rays
sustain organic processes in the fulfillment of no purpose whatsoever, but we
wear hats to protect ourselves from the spill-over effects of temporary
blindness or skin cancer, we use deodorant to avoid sweating in our sophisticated
cultures, and we harness solar energy to power a variety of contraptions; nor
do we content ourselves with the childish mental projections of astrology, when
we look up at the inhuman heavens, but we hurl telescopes into space and land
robots on Mars; and so on and so forth. We make the cosmos our home by
extending our minds and bodies into the outer reaches of the unknown: we give
the nooks and crannies of the undead god silly names that elevate us, since our
experience of what it’s like to be human anchors the metaphors, and we manually
reshape our environment, physically erasing nature’s monstrous visage with
reminders of our more comprehensible creativity, so that when we traverse any
of our villages or cities, we walk through a House of Mirrors. We look at a hut
or a skyscraper instead of a cave or a mountain, and we replace our fear of the
cosmic creation of patterns from quantum chaos, with the homeliness of
intelligent design, of a person’s mind-controlled body which purposefully tames
and beautifies its surroundings.
We
preserve our self-esteem by pretending that technology has merely the practical
function of efficiently achieving our goals, whereas the existential
significance of technology betrays that lofty pragmatism. Before we can be gods
who magically recreate the world in our image, we ought to be panic-stricken,
all-too-clever critters that have opened Pandora’s Box just by opening our eyes
and beholding the alien landscape. Technology, then, is a source of what
existentialists call bad faith, but a source that ironically has the potential
to undercut the delusions that restrict us to an aesthetically inferior way of
life. We fuel our pride when we revel in the technoscientific proof of our
supernatural creativity, but when we reflect on technology’s primordial role as
a mirror that permits us to look out onto anything and see so many traces of
humanity instead of wild nature’s bloodcurdling monstrosity, that is, its
undead complexification, we’re steered away from pragmatic secular humanism,
not to mention anachronistic theism, and towards existential cosmicism.
No comments:
Post a Comment