Dennis Prager is an American syndicated radio host and is
known for his zealous defense of conservatism and Judaism. He often admits that he doesn’t think
God’s existence can be proven, although he adds that he doesn’t think atheism
can be proven either, and yet he likes to say that he comes to his religious
beliefs through toxic effects of secularism, such as the moral bankruptcy of
liberalism and postmodern philosophy. He also likes to say that while atheists
can be knowledgeable and intellectual, they tend to lack wisdom, because wisdom
derives from God. His radio-quality baritone and Jewish affiliation lends him a
wise man’s aura, but reading through some of his articles and listening to some
of his debates and Prager University videos makes for a letdown. His is meant to be the Machiavellian “wisdom”
of a secularized Jew who is too busy making money in business, idolizing
Americanism, and sucking up to American “Christian” conservatives to
demonstrate any concern for philosophical depth or rigor.
Prager’s Two Questions for Atheists
Let’s examine some of Prager’s arguments. He often poses two questions to atheists, which he thinks are the
most important to ask: “Do you hope you are right or wrong [about whether God
exists]?” and “Do you ever doubt your atheism?” While he debates the philosophical
issues with atheists, he says, what really interests him “are the answers to
these two questions.” This is ‘Because only if the atheist responds, “I hope I
am wrong” and “Yes, there have been occasions when I have wondered whether
there really might be a God”—do I believe that I have encountered an individual
who has really thought through his or her atheism. I also believe that I have
probably met a truly decent person.’
If the atheist says she doesn’t hope there’s a God, she’s
revealed that she has a “cold soul,” and so Prager writes, “I respect atheists
who answer that they hope they are wrong. It tells me that they understand the
terrible consequences of atheism: that all existence is random; that there is
no ultimate meaning to life; that there is no objective morality—right and
wrong are subjective personal or societal constructs; that when we die, there
is nothing but eternal oblivion, meaning, among other things, that one is never
reconnected with any loved ones; and there is no ultimate justice in the
universe—murderers, torturers and their victims have identical fates: nothing.”
And if she doesn’t ever doubt her atheism, Prager says, the
atheist shows she’s more dogmatic than theists who frequently doubt some of
their religious beliefs. Thus Prager writes, “When experiencing, seeing or
reading about terrible human suffering, all of us who believe in God have on
occasion doubted our faith. So, I asked the atheists, how is it that when you
see a baby born or a spectacular sunset, or hear a Mozart symphony, or read
about the infinite complexity of the human brain—none of these has ever
prompted you to wonder whether there really might be a God?”
Prager is right, more or less, about the dire implications
of philosophical naturalism, but he hasn’t thought through the implications of
theism if he thinks that positing God remedies our existential situation—as
Kierkegaard and the other religious existentialists would have pointed out to
him. To begin with, Prager’s notion that “all existence is random,” given
atheism, is a strawman, since atheists are typically naturalists and
naturalists posit natural order, patterns, and even invariances or nomic
relations. There’s randomness in nature, but there are also regularities subject
to rational explanations. If reality were
ultimately mental rather than some living-dead flow of matter and physicality,
that is, were God the metaphysically primary cause of everything else, there
would be no reason why existence shouldn’t be fundamentally random, since God
could always change his mind or act on a whim. Mindless matter has no
freedom or emotional impulse to unfold against its nature or to reverse course
out of spite or jealousy. Only credulity and superstitious deference to
orthodox interpretations of scriptures, based on taking human autocrats as
models of the supernatural boss in the sky, would lead
theists to presume that if God exists, the universe is secure and we have
nothing to worry about as long as we follow certain Iron Age commandments. What
would stop God from creating infinite universes and disposing of them at will
or as inspired by an alien aesthetics, as depicted in Olaf Stapledon’s Star Maker? What could prevent God from
doing absolutely anything he wants for no reason we could possibly understand,
as is the lesson of the Book of Job? Only were we naively anthropocentric would we think that God’s logic should align with our mammalian reasoning, that
we’re “made in God’s image.” Only a sanctimonious blowhard would boast that her
interpretation of poetic scripture and thus of God’s alleged intentions is the
only valid one.
So Prager has it
backwards: if you want to feel half-way secure in the world, without having
to resort to a leap of faith, you’d prefer the world to be fundamentally mindless,
since that would remove the element of arbitrary choice from how the universe
works. Quantum mechanics and the ultimate source of natural order may be
mysterious on naturalistic grounds (as they are on theistic ones too, since
positing a miracle or an eternal, supernatural person doesn’t explain
anything), but at least macroscopic matter and physicality would have no
metaphysical basis for inexplicably reversing themselves. Sure, the theist will
assert that God keeps his word, that
he’s perfect and that he loves us and so would never mislead us or act without
good reason. But even Prager concedes (as in his debate with Christopher
Hitchens and Dinesh D’Souza, starting at around the 14:14 minute mark) that the
prevalence of unnecessary suffering in the world should mystify the theist. And
as he says in his debate with Michael Shermer (at the 13:45 minute mark;
Shermer is next to useless), he makes only two leaps of faith: that God exists
and that God is good. Of course, Prager’s notion of “goodness” is
anthropocentric, so what he means by calling God good is that God won’t do
anything in the end to offend our
conceptions of justice and fair play, such as holding out the promise of our
eternal life, in religious revelation, and going back on his word or changing
his mind. In any case, Prager admits that this adorable restriction of God’s
nature and character to the self-interested limits of our sense of propriety is
just a leap of faith. So as far as reason is concerned, the theist shouldn’t be so comfortable, after
all, given her belief that she lives in a universe controlled by a lone,
all-powerful guy with absolute discretion to do whatever he wants.
Certainly, our experience of human dictators shouldn’t inspire confidence that
God would be trustworthy—or remotely benevolent or sane, for that matter.
I’ll turn to the question of morality in the next section,
but this point about the gratuitous characterization of God in terms that are
ideal from a human-centered viewpoint applies to Prager’s other assumptions
about the implications of atheism, quoted above. There needn’t be an afterlife
if there’s no God (although there are plenty of sci-fi scenarios that allow for
such an afterlife, as in the case of all-powerful transhumans in the distant
future being able to resurrect or simulate past life forms; see, for example,
Fyodorov’s cosmism and Clarke’s and Baxter’s novel, The Light of Other Days), but there’s likewise no need for God to grant us eternal life;
rather, theists merely have the need to grasp at that straw, but that wouldn’t
obligate God to care about us or to be a humanitarian. Indeed, were we made in
God’s image, we could expect God to double-cross us, since we frequently do so
to each other. If instead God’s perfect, he must be alien and inhuman, and so
we have no idea what he’d do for us. Divine revelation doesn’t help, since interpreting the scriptures is subjective and leads
to the same problem of relativism which Prager thinks besets liberal
secularism.
As for Prager’s second question, his error is similar to that
of the political centrist who thinks that the social truth is found midway between
conservatism and liberalism, that each side therefore has an identical
obligation to compromise, since the two sides are equally extreme. Likewise,
Prager assumes what amounts to agnosticism, which says that God’s existence is
neither provable nor disprovable, that theism and atheism are therefore equally
arbitrary, and that the theist and the atheist both ought to recognize the
unknowability of whether there’s a God and so should wonder once in a while
whether they’re on the right track. Indeed, to extend Kierkegaard’s point about
fear and trembling, Prager might suggest the atheist ought to be angst-ridden in pondering God’s
possibility, given that reason doesn’t settle the matter either way.
Here everything hinges on what the theist means by “God.”
The more you define that word according to want you want God to be, the more incoherent your religious conceptions are
bound to be, and so the more atheism wins by rational standards, if only by
default, because the theistic side doesn’t then bother showing up. Lack of
belief in something self-contradictory, vacuous, or childishly construed is
automatically the rational, responsible position on the question whether that X
which is simultaneously not-X or which is otherwise plainly absurd and outdated
exists. In that case, we should expect the theist to be constantly wrestling
with doubts about her anachronistic religious beliefs, but the atheist has no
comparable basis for doubting the merit of the opposite beliefs.
If God is stripped of his personhood and thought of as some
pseudonatural Force, then indeed agnosticism might be more reasonable—except
for the fact that the atheist would have recourse to Laplace’s response, that
there’s no need for the God hypothesis. In other words, if you think of God as
only a (mostly empty) First Cause, the psychological question of our degree of certainty
about whether such a cause exists is irrelevant, since the discourse will have
shifted to science-centered territory. All that matters, then, would be whether
theism is useful, not philosophically or religiously True. Finally, if you define
“God” along more mystical, obscure lines, so that God becomes a mere cosmicist
reminder of our finitude and fragility, a metaphysical placeholder representing
the sublime and the numinous, namely that which forever transcends our
comprehension, the atheist would have no reason to doubt the existence of this
“God,” since these sobering properties are eminently found in the world as it’s
conceived by the philosophical naturalist.
The shakiness of Prager’s argument is apparent from his
examples which are supposed to show that agnosticism ought to compel the theist
and the atheist equally to compromise with self-doubts. The problem of evil and
unnecessary suffering should give the theist pause, he writes, and as for the
miracles that are supposed to shock the atheist into wondering whether maybe
the universe was after all created by an invisible, everlasting guy, he cites “a
baby born or a spectacular sunset,” the hearing of “a Mozart symphony” or “the
infinite complexity of the human brain.” He could just as easily and
fruitlessly have added that our planet seems to be at the center of the
universe. You see, Prager’s agnosticism leads him to prize intuition as our only recourse when logic and empirical evidence
prove inconclusive. So if a baby’s birth seems
miraculous and wonderful, even though that phenomenon has been thoroughly
explained without the God hypothesis, the atheist is supposed to be fanatical
unless she entertains second thoughts. As we’ll see later, though, Prager’s
appeal to intuition is biased since he trusts only socially conservative ones
and dismisses the liberal’s as nonsensical. On the contrary, the upshot of the
Scientific Revolution is that when it comes to telling us about the real world,
all our treasured intuitions are
dubious.
The Status of Religious and Secular Moralities
Of course, Prager does think theism is useful; indeed, he
proclaims that theism is the only basis of morality. In his video, called “If there’s no God, Murder isn’t Wrong,” he claims to demonstrate the
“fact” that “Without a God who is the source of morality, morality is just a
matter of opinion.” By contrast, he says, for the theist, morality is
“objective” and “absolute,” which are two qualities he doesn’t distinguish but
conflates to misrepresent the issue as being about whether morality is real or
just arbitrary and made up like mere opinions. “Without God,” he says, “there
are no moral facts” and so the wrongness of murder can’t be scientifically
proven.
Plato’s Euthyphro dilemma showed over two thousand years ago
that the objectivity of morality is a red
herring. You need only consult your dictionary to see that whether morality
is objective is irrelevant. According to Dictionary.com and with my emphases,
“objective” means (1) “not influenced by personal
feelings, interpretations, or prejudice; based on facts; unbiased,” (2) “intent
upon or dealing with things external to
the mind rather than with thoughts or feelings, as a person or a book,” (3)
“being the object of perception or thought; belonging to the object of thought
rather than to the thinking subject
(opposed to subjective),” or (4) “of or relating to something that can be
known, or to something that is an object or a part of an object; existing independent of thought or an observer as part of reality.”
What these definitions have in common is that objectivity is
about how things are in themselves irrespective of what anyone thinks or feels about them. The theist says morality comes
not from us but from God. Nevertheless, God is supposed to be a person, so
theistic morality is necessarily as subjective, albeit not necessarily as
flawed, as the secular morality that we arrive at due to our best judgments. Just because you swap God for a human
person, doesn’t mean you establish that morality is independent of thought of
feeling; all you show is that morality is independent of our thoughts and feelings.
The closest these definitions come to showing what Prager
would want them to show is where (1) says that objectivity has to do with the facts as opposed to various fallible
sources of judgment. By definition, God would be infallible. Nevertheless, as
Plato showed, saying that God deems certain actions moral or immoral doesn’t
mean that his judgment is necessarily fact-based. As Plato asked, is murder
wrong because God decrees it so or does he decree it because murder is
independently wrong? Only in the latter case would murder be wrong as an
objective fact, as a matter of how things are in themselves regardless of what
anyone says, and yet in that case God wouldn’t be the source of morality. If
morality were objective, God’s task would be merely to confirm as much with his flawless cognitive faculties, not to provide
the ground of morality. And if morality is as it is independent of anyone’s
judgment, the theist loses the upper hand, since at best, God would be epistemically useful to our
deliberations about morality, not metaphysically so. We flawed creatures might
defer to God’s moral judgment, assuming his knowledge is perfect, but morality
would still be possible without that reflection in divine reasoning and thus without God’s existence. We
might just never come to know about
what’s moral were it not for divine revelation (of which there clearly is none
in our history).
So the objectivity of
morality would hardly be the theist’s friend. If morality is fact-based, it
could just as easily be so on atheistic grounds. Moreover, if actions are right
or wrong as a matter of objective fact, established as such independent of any mind, the moralist promptly runs
into the wall of the naturalistic fallacy
in trying to infer the prescription from what must be the mere description of
that objective fact.
By contrast, for those interested in the least bit of
rigour, “absolute” means among other things, (1) “free from imperfection;
complete; perfect,” (2) “free from restriction or limitation; not limited in
any way,” (3) “unrestrained or unlimited by a constitution, counterbalancing
group, etc., in the exercise of governmental power, especially when arbitrary
or despotic,” (4) “viewed independently; not comparative or relative; ultimate;
intrinsic,” (5) “positive; certain.” These definitions seem closer to what a
theist would want to say about morality, especially a conservative one like
Prager. What Prager wants to say, then, is that only if God exists and at least
tells us about what’s moral would that morality be absolute (not objective) by
being perfect, complete, ultimate, and certain. We can be confident only about
religious morality, as opposed to the secular kind which degenerates into
postmodern squabbles that can never be resolved, because the liberal takes each
person’s opinion to be as authoritative as anyone else’s.
The key here, then, seems to be the hidden, political sense
of (3). Having been chastened about speaking of morality’s “objectivity,” the
theist should switch to the need for morality’s absoluteness in contrast to the
supposed travesty of secular relativism. This is to say that the issue is about
the decidability of moral questions. God functions then not as the ground of
morality’s being, as in the above fiasco of supposing that morality is “objective,”
but as the dictator who has the last word because of a mere difference in power
between God and his subjects. Likewise, Kim Jong-un’s decree is absolute in
North Korea. Again, God’s perfect reasoning and knowledge would be irrelevant,
since those faculties could establish, at best, morality’s basis in mind-independent
fact which God merely confirms and which would thus deprive the theist of the
moral high ground she craves. What’s needed, rather, is God’s domination of the
world he created and could destroy without warning, as shown in the last
section. What matters to the theist with respect to morality is that theistic
morality is politically absolute.
The reason, then, this religious morality would be “perfect”
is that none of us would dare say otherwise, just as no ordinary North Korean
would even dream of opposing their dictator. Similarly, God’s morality would be
absolute in the sense of extending everywhere, “free from limitation,” because
God’s rule would be unlimited, given his unique omnipotence. God’s morality
would be “ultimate” because there would be no higher authority than God, and we
could be “certain” about this morality for the same reason North Koreans are
certain that they have the best leader in the world, this certainty being a
matter merely of the social utility of being brainwashed for fear of offending
the tyrant.
What, though, of Prager’s substantive claim that morality
without God is a matter only of opinion? Again, the possibility that morality
is objective and thus fact-based (and potentially natural) shows that atheistic
morality needn’t be decided just by opinion, which is to say that Prager’s
discussion of morality is incoherent. But putting that aside, let’s suppose
that secular morality is subjective and thus decided not by any reasoning but
just by opinion. This is to say that secular morality would be a matter of
taste, that it would be irrational and ultimately faith-based. Does Prager mean
to insinuate, then, that the theist has the least advantage in this context,
when Prager himself concedes that he accepts the notion of God’s goodness only
by a leap of faith? The theist trusts in some ancient scriptures or religious
experience to dictate her values, whereas the secularist trusts in the writings
of some philosophers or framers of a political constitution or Hollywood or corporate
propaganda to dictate her values. They’re thus on equal footing as far as the
wise, authentic, Kierkegaardian theist is concerned. Alas, Prager isn’t one of
those.
Prager’s Religion is American Conservatism
Why, then, aside from his confusion about objectivity, does
Prager presume he has the obvious upper hand in this regard? The answer is that
his American form of modern Judaism reduces to social conservatism, since that
and most other kinds of Judaism are practically atheological and functionally
atheistic or at least agnostic. That is, these Jews are interested mainly in
wisdom in something like the Aristotelian respect (learning to flourish on
earth), not in speculating about God and the afterlife. This is why Prager
happily appeals to agnosticism, because what matters to him isn’t whether
religious beliefs are rationally justifiable, but whether religion is needed to
live the good life. He takes from Judaism mainly the emphasis on morality,
which as I show elsewhere derives from the ancient Jewish
bastardization of Zoroastrian monotheism, and for a Jew in his milieu, having grown
up in a Modern Orthodox family in America in the 1950s, this morality can only
be conservative. In short, Prager’s
religion is effectively just the ideology of Americanism. By “Americanism,”
I mean the worst stereotype of what outsiders think of Americans, which
conservative trolls like Prager the radio shock jockey ironically insist on substantiating.
Prager’s tales from the Torah provide so much sanctimony and colour commentary for
the conservative American values that have little especially to do with Judaism
(except for the fact that some Jews used to run Hollywood and still have an
outsized influence on that dream factory). What
matters to Prager, then, is mainly the American culture war between liberals
and conservatives. And he presumes he has the upper hand not so much
against atheists in general, but against liberals.
Thus, he can tolerate the faith-basis of morality, but what appalls him is the
particular leap of faith into morality taken by liberals.
Notice, for example, how he says in his discussion with Shermer (starting at around the 8:36 minute mark), that he comes to
theistic belief through what he calls the failure of secular culture, and more
specifically through the failure of the secularism he was taught in college.
And what was the secular “foolishness” and “nonsense” he was taught, which
brought to his mind the Jewish principle that there’s no wisdom (as opposed to
knowledge) without God? He offers some examples in his debate with Hitchens
(see especially the 10:50 minute mark): the “drivel” that “men and women are
basically the same” which “religious people know is nonsense,” “the hysteria of
global warming,” and the notion “that the United States and the Soviet Union
were morally equivalent.” Whatever you may think of these three teachings, they
have much more to do with the American culture war than with theism, let alone
Judaism. Prager’s religion is practically the idol of American conservatism;
there’s just little more to his secularized, agnostic Jewish beliefs than that.
Just look at what he mainly writes and talks about. His videos on his
Prager University website are explicitly directed against liberalism and almost
all espouse social conservative talking points. His columns, too, are
mostly about social or political issues that arise in the American culture war.
But the clincher is his defense of American
Evangelicals for supporting “President” Trump, published February 6, 2018. (This
is only one of numerous other celebrations of Trump’s presidency by Prager.
See, for example, this 2017 article.) Whereas many
castigate these “Christians” for their obvious hypocrisy, moral bankruptcy, and
intellectual hollowness, Prager stands by them, contending that “these attacks
are not biblical, moral or wise.” (There’s that favourite word of his, “wise.”)
This is because, he writes, “Religious Christians and Jews who support Trump
understand that the character of a public leader is quite often less important
than his policies. This is so obvious that only the naive think otherwise. Character
is no predictor of political leadership on behalf of moral causes.” In short,
he writes, “Evangelicals realize that the moral good of defeating the left is
of surpassing importance.” In particular, the choice in 2016 was between Trump
and Hillary Clinton, and he says, “For the record, I believe his character is
superior to hers.”
As far as I can tell, this stance of his gives the game
away. Prager’s reasoning, of course, is specious, since he reduces the question
of sanity to one of character, and is misled to make what
can only be the rankest partisan statement that Hillary Clinton’s character is
worse than Trump’s—even though Trump evidently suffers literally from malignant narcissism. Note that Prager published this
article long after the 2016 campaign, after the mountains of sordid details of
Trump’s inhumanity have come to light. To defend Trump’s “Christian” supporters
after all of this can only be a political act in support of Republican power or
in deference to his side in the petty American culture war. But my point is that these sociopolitical issues
are religious for Prager, because his
version of Judaism is practically a secular ideology which amounts to
Americanism.
Another clue is Prager’s frequent appeal to “wisdom.” He
says, for example, that attacking Trump’s defenders is unwise, because it’s
“naïve” to assume that a leader’s character matters more than the policies at
stake. This is to say that we should expect hypocrisy from political leaders,
because politicians frequently lie, exploiting people’s weaknesses to obtain
political power. Thus, a politician’s character might be part of her illusion
or persona, whereas what matters to the savvy voter is what the leader would
likely do with her power, regardless of what she pretends to be like to get
votes. George W. Bush pretended to be a guy you wanted to have a beer with,
whereas in reality he was an Ivy Leaguer from a rich and powerful family.
Barack Obama pretended to be a transformative figure who would change
Washington, but governed as a cautious centrist. And like Bush, Donald Trump
pretended to an aw-shucks everyman even though he’s a rarified billionaire who
has bottomless contempt for everyone except “winners” in the business and the military.
This is all fine, but
what Prager misses is that a religious person might choose to have higher standards than those of a wannabe
Machiavellian, to identify her religious principles with something other than
such secular political calculation or
“wisdom.” In addition, of course, he misses the fact that betting on the
character of a senile madman and defending Trump on pragmatic grounds is
foolish rather than wise, since such a character in high office will be
monumentally incompetent, capricious, and disloyal, as has come to pass. Any
gains the Republicans make now in terms of crony-capitalistic tax cuts and the
appointment of authoritarian, Bible-toting judges can be erased many times over
after the national backlash against the embarrassment of having had a full-blown
Manchurian candidate for president. That backlash can sweep away not just
Republican power but the moral authority of Evangelical Christians, both of
which the wise man Prager cherishes.
What to make of Prager’s substantive claim, though, that
atheism is dubious because the atheist tends to be liberal and liberalism is so
nonsensical that evidently if you don’t believe in God you’ll believe anything?
This is a gloss on Dostoevsky’s and the Marquis de Sade’s worry that if there’s
no God, anything is permitted. For example, Prager, who is a classical music
enthusiast regards modern artworks as “moronic cartoons that fill our
galleries” (see 1:02:12 into the debate with Hitchens). The obvious response to
this sentiment is the one that Richard Dawkins frequently gives, which is that
the truth can be unpleasant. If God is
dead, many people might be sad or mad, consciously or otherwise, and distressed
people might be expected to produce unsettling art. If this art offends
Prager’s taste, the artist’s adequate response might be merely that blaming the
messenger is obnoxious. Modern art expresses the science-centered
understanding that the universe is godless and that life is fundamentally
absurd. That art will horrify only because it transmits the horror found in an
honest confrontation with the real world. Prager whines about liberal culture because
his archaic religious metanarrative is no longer taken seriously in elite
American circles. He wants to say we should be decent to each other because God
commands it, without realizing that he’s effectively telling us to be childlike
to accept such an uninformed justification—and children are the least
decent of all.
To be sure, liberalism and secular humanism are deeply
problematic, as I’ve attempted to show in numerous writings (see here, here,
here, here, and here for a start). Indeed,
I’ve argued that the boundlessness of late-modern
art has the silver lining of indicating that anything can be interpreted as
art, in which case we end up with a form of pantheism. But old-fashioned
conservatism is hardly the answer to the follies of liberal humanism. Indeed,
the secret of religious conservatism was unveiled by Hobbes’ political
philosophy in which only the myth of
God might be useful in perfecting the conservative’s (that is, the classic
liberal’s) animal mechanisms of social control. Prager’s social conservatism is
simply monstrous, as is evident from his groveling before the literal monster
of “President” Trump. Is such sycophancy wise?
No, Judaism recommends trusting in an authority that can never be toppled,
whereas Trump’s downfall seems inevitable. Subsequently, the sycophants will
have to answer for their being on the wrong side of history. A truly wise,
Machiavellian American, in the sense of someone who cares more about expediency
than philosophical truth or any other higher calling would fudge on the
question of Trump’s fitness for office. Prager,
though, inherits the theist’s pretentiousness while divorcing that attitude
from theological content, so that he ends up pontificating on mere culture war wedge
issues without being concerned with whether any part of his cruel, plutocratic Republican
creed is compatible with an authentic theistic religion. Prager’s Jewish enough not to get caught up
in theistic fundamentalism, that is, in literalizing biblical teachings, but
he’s plenty American enough to be a bigoted, social-Darwinian yahoo.
America’s Secular Origin
Prager thinks that liberalism is morally bankrupt, that
secularism is unwise, and that the founders of America knew this, which is why
to the social structures laid out by the Constitution they added the principle
that morality is founded on religion. No matter how balanced or efficient the
political system, if the people are decadent because they’ve lost faith in God
and thus have no reason to be moral but deem themselves at liberty to do
whatever they want, the society will collapse. Thus, says Prager in his debate
with Shermer, George Washington said in his Farewell Address that morality
requires religion, and Jefferson writes in the Declaration of Independence that
our Creator endowed us with unalienable rights; Prager adds that if the Creator
hadn’t done so, we wouldn’t have such rights (47:45).
This demonstrates that Prager has no clue what was really
going on with the founding of America. More specifically, he seems unaware of
the lesson from Leo Strauss, about the tendency for great writers to include
both exoteric and esoteric messages in their texts. You can see this
distinction at work in the relevant part of Washington’s Farewell Address: “And let us with caution indulge the supposition, that morality can be maintained without religion. Whatever may be conceded to the influence of refined education on minds of peculiar structure--reason and experience both forbid us to expect that National morality can prevail in exclusion of religious principle.” (p.20). Did you catch the distinction between
philosophy ("refined education on minds of peculiar structure") and “reason and experience,” the latter being closer to commonsense
or intuition? Washington implies that the esoteric, hidden truth of the
irrationality of religious beliefs is established by philosophy, that is, by
the rigorous application of reason, but then there’s the pragmatic issue of
what to do about the unenlightened masses, which is to speak of the need for
“National morality.” The masses aren’t at all philosophical, so their morality
must be based on religion. Thus, the government should give the outward
appearance of basing its laws ultimately on some religion so as not to confuse
or to terrify the masses with unsettling philosophical abstractions.
Notice also that Washington connects morality to religion,
not to God. A civic religion will do just as nicely, including the one
practiced by most Americans, including their politicians. Thus, in practice, Americans
worship money, guns, their military, and their Constitution, not Jesus Christ or
Yahweh—of all things! Washington seems to acknowledge the distinction between
theistic and civil religions when he says earlier in the same paragraph, “Religion and morality are indispensable supports. In vain would that man claim the tribute of Patriotism, who should labour to subvert these great Pillars of human happiness.” He doesn’t imply that patriotism, that is,
secular religion or ideology, won’t work at all, but only that patriotism won’t easily substitute for traditional religions. Still, were patriotism, or Americanism, to become a full-blown godless religion or form of idol-worship—which it has for American Evangelicals and materialistic hyper-consumers—there would seem little reason to think patriotism wouldn't do the trick.
As for the Declaration of Independence, a full account of
the Enlightenment-basis of the clause, “that they are endowed by their Creator
with certain unalienable rights, that among these are life, liberty, and the
pursuit of happiness,” is supplied by Chapter 7 of Matthew Stewart’s book, Nature’s God: The Heretical Origins of the
American Republic. Stewart shows how the idea of unalienable rights went
from Hobbes to Spinoza to Locke to Jefferson. So Prager errs badly when he
concedes, in talking with Shermer, that the founders “weren’t orthodox
Christians,” while he maintains that they were “God-centered men” and that
“their god was the God of the Bible.” On
the contrary, being intellectual elites of their period, theirs was the God of
the philosophers, the God which Spinoza identified with Nature. The rights
in question weren’t anything like moral commandments but were inherent powers or
tendencies and were granted, as Hobbes put it, by the laws of nature. (As
Stewart points out on p.354, in Jefferson’s first draft, he called the rights
“inherent.”) This is why these rights can’t be taken away, because they’re part
of our nature as living creatures. To attempt to take them away is only to
change the topic. We have the natural right to our life, for example, because
nature endows us with the power to maintain and defend our life. As Hobbes put
it, the punishment for attempting to violate that right to life is enforced not
by a personal God but by natural cause and effect: if I attempt to harm you,
you will defend yourself and attempt to harm me in turn. Nature likewise frees us
in so far as the powers of reason and language make us autonomous creatures,
able to control ourselves and plan for the future. And Nature drives us to
attempt to be happy, by providing us with desires which motivate us to act in
our self-interest.
But Prager will protest that Jefferson says those rights are
given by our “Creator,” and since he capitalizes that word, he must be
referring to the personal deity of the Judeo-Christian tradition. This is as
empty as saying that since philosophers or theologians capitalize the name of
the ultimate power in their philosophy, be it the “Absolute,” the “First Cause,”
or whatever else, they too must be referring to the personal God of some
monotheistic religion—as though there were no problem deriving Christianity,
say, from Aquinas’s Aristotelian proofs of the existence of an unnatural First
Cause! What Prager misses is that Jefferson identifies that “Creator” in the preceding
sentence: the time had come, Jefferson wrote, for the American colonists “to
assume among the powers of the earth, the separate and equal station to which
the Laws of Nature and of Nature's God entitle them.” The Creator in question,
then, wasn’t the God of Abraham or of Moses, Noah, or Jesus. It was the God of
Nature in the same sense in which Thor is thought of as the god of Thunder, or
Aphrodite as the goddess of Love or Lucifer as the god of lies. And who speaks
for the God of nature? Not priests but scientists and philosophers who mean to
establish what Hobbes called the “empire of reason.”
This much alone should be conceded to the likes of Prager,
that capitalizing “Creator” makes for a fortunate, Straussian ambiguity. The
vulgar masses will take Jefferson to be referring to Yahweh or to the Father of
Jesus Christ, whereas the philosophically informed will understand the true
meaning that should be hidden, which is that to speak so oddly of “Nature’s
God” is to speak implicitly of “the God of Nature,” and that that latter phrase
is ambiguous since “of” can be possessive (as in “the government of America”)
or it can imply an identity (as in “the country of America”). Thus, to speak of
the God of Nature could be taken to mean that God belongs to Nature just as the
wallet of John belongs to John—which, of course, would seem strange, since the
Jew or Christian would much prefer to reverse the terms, to say that Nature
belongs to God, in which case Jefferson should have written “God’s Nature.”
Alas for Prager and for the rest of the unphilosophical masses, Jefferson
didn’t say that, which raises the specter of the other, pantheistic meaning,
which is that for Jefferson “God” and “Nature” are two names for the same
thing. That’s evidently why he capitalized not only “Creator” but “Nature” as
well as “Laws of Nature.”
This is why America’s philosophical founders don’t appeal to
anything like the Ten Commandments to establish human rights. It’s only the
Laws of Nature that are at issue for them, because the rights in question were
considered natural, not divine. Indeed, divine rights were part of the monarchy
from which the colonists were declaring their independence. This is also why
personal liberty was so important to the founding documents, and why the
American government was designed to maximize that freedom. If morality were
“objective” and fact-based as Prager says, we wouldn’t be free but would be
God’s slaves, just as we’re slaves to gravity or to chemical reactions because
these things are likewise objective. If our moral rights come from God and the king
governs on God’s behalf, we would have no right to question the king, let alone
to fight for our political independence. Thus, Jefferson writes that
“Governments”—which he also capitalizes—and not some supernatural gods “secure
our rights,” and that the Governments in turn derive “their just powers from
the consent of the governed”—not from any Holy Scripture or religious
experience or authority, but from the freely given approval of the governed. So
the very structure of a democratic republic is utterly secular, which is why so
many Muslims are hostile to this aspect of Western culture.
Humanism and Totalitarianism, Morality and Blessedness
To see more deeply into what’s at stake here, consider John
Ralston Saul’s way of distinguishing between morality and blessedness, in Voltaire’s Bastards. “An individual,” he
writes,
is someone who takes upon himself an understanding of what is moral and who monitors his own conduct. A man who depends upon blessedness is one who relies upon God and his representatives to define morality and to enforce it. He is a child of God—a ward who would not dream of claiming personal responsibility. The individual is more like a child who has grown up and left home. Either that or, having killed God, man was obliged to fill the resulting void. In either case he assumed the powers of moral judgment previously limited to divinities. (468-9)
So Prager and the exoteric monotheist, that is, the one who
is ignorant according to philosophical standards, are advocating blessedness
rather than morality, all their bluster about “moral absolutes”
notwithstanding. And the American project, of course, belonging not at all to
the medieval period but to the subsequent Age of Reason, is about creating
governmental structures that secure genuine moral rights, where these are
understood in terms of their existential context as entailing a terrifying form
of personal freedom. The autonomous and thus isolated individual whose consent
alone gives legitimacy to the government takes the place of God as the judge of
morality, if not as its sole source. Natural
rights or powers are supposed to be the origins of morality, but as to how
these powers are codified and enforced, that’s up to the individual, which is
why the American government is set up to allow the individual to do whatever
she wants as long as she doesn’t become a nuisance. By contrast, in
Prager’s world we ought to seek the blessed state of servitude in Heaven, in
which freedom of choice is lost and we surrender forever to God’s majesty.
That’s the Dark Age mentality, not the enlightened American one over which
Prager has no claim.
As Saul points out, that distinction between morality and
blessedness comes from Thomas Mann’s The
Magic Mountain, in which Mann’s character, Naphta (a Jew-turned Jesuit and Hegelian
Marxist), criticizes the secular humanism of Settembrini, calling it “bourgeoisiedom”
and “Philistinism,” which he says are opposed to religion. Another character (the
protagonist Hans Castorp) suggests that the antithesis “between life and
religion went back to that between time and eternity. Only in time was there
progress; in eternity there was none, nor any politics or eloquence either.
There, so to speak, one laid one’s head back in God, and closed one’s eyes. And
that was the difference between religion and morality” (463). Again, Prager’s
talk of objective morality lands him on the side of laying “one’s head back in
God,” which is very far from the American founders’ insistence on maximizing
individual freedom to develop their natural rights as Americans see fit, not as
commanded by any deity. Naphta grants, “There was much to admire in the
monumental respectability, the majestic Philistinism of the middleclass
consciousness. But one must never forget that as it stood, straddle-legged,
firmly planted on earth, hands behind the back, chest well out, it was the
embodiment of irreligion.” Likewise, America itself stands as inherently irreligious, as far as Prager
should be concerned.
Mann develops the metaphysical or mythical basis of humanism
further: God and the Devil, he writes, were considered ‘two distinct persons or
principles, with “life” as a bone of contention between them—which, by the by,
was just the way the Middle Ages had envisaged them. But in reality, God and
the Devil were at one in being opposed to life, to bourgeoisiedom, reason and
virtue, since they together represented the religious principle.’ And the point
about individualism, morality, and blessedness is that the proponent of this
naturalistic, monistic humanism, which takes morality to be personal, subjective,
and thus opposed to traditional religion should still distinguish between
morality and blessedness. Here’s the passage Saul draws from:
A society in which life was stupidly conceived as an end in itself, with no questions asked about its ulterior meaning and purpose, was governed by a tribal and social ethic, indeed, a vertebrate morality, if you liked, but certainly not by individualism. For individualism belonged, singly and solely, in the realm of the religious and mystical, in the so-called “morally chaotic All” [that is, in godless, amoral nature conceived of as independent of both God and the Devil, Good and Evil]. And this [humanistic, individualistic] morality of Herr Settembrini’s, what was it, what did it want? It was life-bound, and thus entirely utilitarian; it was pathetically unheroic. Its end and aim was to make men grow old and happy, rich and comfortable—and that was all there was to it. And this Philistine philosophy, this gospel of work and reason, served Herr Settembrini as an ethical system. As far as he, Naphta, was concerned, he would continue to deny that it was anything but the sheerest and shabbiest bourgeoisiedom. (464)
So Prager’s condemnation of liberalism and postmodernism in late-modern
America attests to the secular origins of that country. Precisely because the
founders were philosophical humanists and saw natural tendencies or “rights” as
the basis of individual freedom and of legitimate political rule, they inadvertently
designed a society that led inexorably to the “moral decline” that Prager
decries. As Saul puts it, in failing to distinguish between morality and
blessedness, that is, between the heroic attempt at retaining intellectual
integrity in the face of God’s death, on the one hand, and a retreat to
blissful ignorance and servitude, on the other, the founders didn’t foresee
that America would yield a secular form
of blessedness, such as the mindless political correctness we see today on
the left. It wasn’t as Prager says in his debate with Shermer, that the
founders understood the masses to be corrupt so that they needed theistic
religion as a crutch. Of course, those Americans who need that crutch are free
to employ it, but what’s distinctly American is the citizen’s right to be free from religion, because that freedom is
granted not by the God of traditional religions, but by Natural Right, by the
God of Nature (the God which is Nature).
Just as Nietzsche spoke of the Last Man who is today’s
infamous beta male, Thomas Mann saw that the Enlightenment ideal of individual
liberty—“this gospel of work and reason”—is natural and thus utilitarian and
ultimately philistine or bourgeois. From Prager’s traditional religious
standpoint of old-fashioned “blessedness,” secular America no longer stands for
anything. But this is only to describe
the essence of America as the latter has always embodied the subversive
principles of philosophical reason. Secular
culture doesn’t decline so much as its horrific truth unfolds as its citizens
are free to bounce between distractions, untethered to religious lies. Of course Americans don’t stand for
anything; that’s what it means to be free!—free even from the ground you had
taken for granted and which would dictate exactly how you should live in the
manner of a religious creed. Like North Korea or the Soviet Union, such a
divinely planned society would be “objectively moral” and thus “stupidly
conceived as an end in itself,” leaving no room for questions from the adults
in the room. Instead, the American founders
assumed only the ground of natural rights,
which empower Americans (and everyone else) to defend their life and to seek
their happiness almost wherever they can find it.
In short, Prager can lay claim only to the caricature of Americanism, not to the humanism that
founded Western society which Europe lost and recaptured, and which was applied
most radically in the founding of the United States. True American patriotism
for the esoteric few who understand what’s really going on would consist not
even in waving the flag, praying to the US military, or drinking Starbucks
coffee daily as dictated by some American civic religion, but in learning to
stomach the inanities of phony wise men like Dennis Prager.
Whoa, this is really a tour de force.
ReplyDeleteI've never thought about it, but early on, you make a point I haven't thought much about: The Universe doesn't operate in a way that is consistent with the way the God of the Old Testament operates. Once processes are set up, they more or less continue, at least until a threshhold is reached where those processes pass into another stage.
This is completely different than the Old Testament God (therefore the Jewish God, really), who makes decisions based on emotion and will sometimes change his mind based on emotions if he sees a mistake. The Deluge story contains two of these decisions (actually 3, which I'll get to): First Yahweh decides humanity was a mistake and wipes us out, more or less, then he decides he won't do it again.
Immediately before the Deluge, he also decides to change the number of years a person can live from 1000 to 120.
The God of the Old Testament would, theoretically, be capable of seeing something he set up, like maybe tectonic plates, and say, "I hadn't considered that earthquakes could result because of this arrangement and kill people who have done nothing wrong" (in areas with more than 5 good people, which he claims in genesis he won't wipe out), "and I am now moved to tinker with tectonic plates to fix this."
There's a station here in town that plays Prager and company on it, and their arguments do generally follow the "atheists are miserable" line of thinking, usually with heavy political overtones. I don't generally find their line of thinking convincing, although I generally call myself an agnostic. That's because I don't know anything at all, but I have no reason to believe that if there is an intelligence behind everything, it bears ANY relationship to the myths humanity has dreamed up.
Thanks. Prager doesn't seem to take a strict line on biblical interpretation. The Bible's all open to being metaphorical, since he's mainly concerned with the conservative's pragmatic take on religion: we need to be religious for society to function.
DeleteBut the general contrast between theism and naturalism stands. Whatever God may have done, as recorded in whichever scripture or in none, if the ultimate explanation of everything is theistic, events would indeed be less regular than they are (unless we take the deistic view that God exists but has virtually nothing to do with how the universe operates). Otherwise, it means nothing to personalize the First Cause. So Prager does have it backwards.