[The following is an email exchange I had with a
philosophical theist known as Darwin Skeptic. He defended the proposition that
philosophy supports theism better than it does atheism, while I argued against
that proposition. We each wrote an opening statement and then several replies.
We gave ourselves around a three-page limit for each message. For this
presentation of the exchange, I cleaned up Darwin Skeptic’s typos and grammar a
little, for the sake of readability. You can read his original messages on his
Facebook page. I’d like to thank Darwin Skeptic for participating in the
discussion/debate.]
*****
Ben Cain’s Opening Statement:
Philosophy, the relatively independent, objective exercise
of reason in response to profound questions can address theism or any
other subject, but it doesn’t support theism well, by making theistic beliefs more rational than atheistic ones.
Atheism is more rational than theism, as far as philosophers are typically
concerned. Not everything that philosophers address is illuminated by their
ruminations, because unlike science, philosophy is partly artistic and
literary, which means it includes speculations and rhetorical rationalizations
of cultural prejudices. At its best, though, philosophers provide arguments or
illustrations that revolutionize culture or that at least separate the
enlightened intellectuals from the hoi polloi. Analytic philosophers currently
focus on science and rigorous analysis, minimizing speculation and rhetoric and
thus the artistic side of philosophy, at the cost of making their tedious,
hyper-detailed writings culturally irrelevant since they’ve had to overlook the
bigger issues.
In any case, even before offering an atheistic argument or
looking at any theistic proof that a religious philosopher might provide, we
shouldn’t expect philosophy to establish that a personal creator of the
universe exists. After all, Western philosophy grew out of a rejection of
popular religion. From Thales to Aristotle, the ancient Greek philosophers
ridiculed the popular notions of gods. The Presocratics overthrew the Olympian
pantheon, crediting various material or impersonal powers with being the
foundations of all other things. They thus made nonsense of the self-serving
metaphors we naively proffer to humanize that which would plainly have to be
unlike anything in nature, to be the precondition of all knowable categories
and particulars, including persons. Plato’s Parable of the Cave famously
substitutes goodness for God. Aristotle’s divine being, the primary cause or
unmoved mover, retained the personal quality of being able to think, but only
because the essence of this being is to reflect on itself. Aristotle’s theology
is thus deistic rather than theistic: his God doesn’t create nature but only
inspires it as its final cause or purpose, as opposed to being nature’s
efficient, mechanical cause. Aristotle’s deity can’t think about or perceive
anything other than itself, because doing so would render it imperfect and thus
it would cease to exist as the eternal, perfect being which all lower beings
look up to.
Such is an example of a philosopher’s god. Of course,
Aristotle was only meditating on the celestial motions of what we now know are
planets, not perfect persons in any way. But the point is that philosophical
reflection on the question of theism in the West has historically acted as a corrective
to the intuitive, emotional, faith-based conceptions of divinity. Vulgar
religion isn’t argumentative; instead, it’s tribal, the gods being mental
projections that celebrate the character of the believers’ culture. To
paraphrase the ancient Greek philosopher Xenophanes, if horses or lions could
believe in gods, their gods would look like horses or lions. Likewise,
aggressive cultures worship angry, jealous gods that threaten to annihilate
their worshippers if they don’t conquer some earthly region or other. And as
Nietzsche pointed out, victimized people such as the early Christians worship a
forgiving deity that prefers weakness to strength, poverty to wealth, modesty
to pride. Christianity thus begins with slave morality, because popular,
exoteric theism in general is a pre-reflective cultural expression quite
inseparable from its religious practices. Indeed, it’s philosophy that
distinguishes theistic beliefs from the religion so that the religious ideas
can be scrutinized without any social commitment to the religion.
In the West, then, philosophy has historically challenged
conventional wisdom in so far as the latter was propped up by prejudices and
mass confusions. For that reason Socrates was executed, and so he became
the secular Christ figure, the martyr for the elite exercise of reason on
behalf of truths which the mob is unwilling to accept, including the truths of
naturalism and atheism. Ancient Greco-Roman philosophy was reborn in Europe
during the Renaissance, after what historians call the Middle Ages. Why the
division rather than historical continuity? Because what passed for philosophy
during the Middle Ages was dogmatic and in the hands of the Roman Catholic
Church which was opposed to philosophy as such; indeed, the Church effectively
demonized philosophy and science as witchcraft and the like, because free-thinking
tended to depart from Church teachings. The essence of philosophy was thus a
crime punishable by death. For example, the Aristotelian proposition that God
can’t think about anything other than himself was banned by the Church in 1270,
and between 1210 and 1277 the Church banned many other philosophical
statements. But these bans proved ineffective, and despite Aquinas’s grand
synthesis of Christianity and Aristotelianism, which was meant to tame the
latter for the glory of the former, the act of reading the ancient texts gave
some Scholastics an inkling of genuine philosophy. They turned into skeptics
who denied that reason could support faith, since they believed reason couldn’t
even prove that the external world exists. These skeptics countered the
rationalists who adhered to the Church’s bans by confining themselves to
pondering how God could act contrary to the condemned parts of Aristotle’s
philosophy. All of the Scholastics’ arguments, though, were necessarily limited
and often whispered rather than written, since they had to be acceptable to the
Church for both the books and the authors to avoid being burned. For example,
Nicholas of Autrecourt had to recant his skepticism and burn all his writings
in 1347.
When more of the ancient texts became available towards the
end of the Medieval Period, they sparked a full-blown humanistic revolution in
Europe that set off the Age of Reason, which included the rise of modern
science and the Enlightenment, the latter being the enforcing of secular philosophy
to establish a culture of liberal humanism. Enlightenment philosophers were
authentically philosophical because they were free to pursue ideas wherever
they led. By contrast, the classic theistic proofs by Aquinas and the
Scholastic philosophers were stale and strained, because their approach to
reason in general was artificially narrow-minded. (Aquinas even admitted as
much on his death bed, calling his life’s work so much “straw.”) Unlike
Socrates, the Church’s intellectuals didn’t love knowledge more than their
skins; those that did were the pagans and heretics from Hypatia to Bruno who
were tortured and murdered by the orthodox Christians. In between the Ages of
Faith and Reason there was a grey area populated by such figures as Descartes,
Leibniz, Spinoza, Locke, and even Newton and Kant. Being men of their time when
the church was still politically powerful, these philosophers and scientists
were partly dogmatists, but they were also partly free thinkers. Most early
modern intellectuals thus argued for both esoteric theism (that is, for a
version of theism or deism which doesn’t sit well with popular religion, the
closer you examine it, seeing through the philosopher’s obfuscations and noble
lies) and liberal secular humanism, because philosophy was still once
again finding its footing. That development culminated in the rabid naturalism
of Nietzsche who predicted the downfall of philosophy itself in our period of
hypermodern malaise.
So the history of Western philosophy should make us
skeptical of philosophical theism. The use of reason in defense of the popular
conception of gods, as being flawless persons who create and miraculously
intervene in nature, tends to be disingenuous. Why? Because there’s
no reason to expect that logic should align with intuition and emotion, and the
popular, theistic (as opposed to deistic, pantheistic, or mystical) conceptions
of gods plainly flow from the latter. When intellectuals begin thinking
freely (and thus philosophically) about theological matters, they inevitably
discover all sorts of gross errors, incoherencies, and other absurdities in the
conventional beliefs. The mob of believers isn’t interested in whether their
religion is rationally justifiable: they want to believe in their gods
because doing so makes them feel better about life and death, and unites their
community in a way that affords its members the chance to be happy. Therefore,
the mob doesn’t include philosophers, because authentic intellectuals (as
opposed to dogmatists and demagogues) stand apart from the crowd, as their
liberated thoughts inevitably have more or fewer subversive implications which
render these intellectuals unpopular.
As partly artistic and rhetorical as it is, compared to
science itself, and thus as capable as it is of arguing for anything under the
sun, philosophy is still ill-suited to establishing the rational superiority of
theism to atheism. The point here is akin to the aphorism about the danger of
trusting in the God of the Gaps. Some theists defend their religion by locating
the work of their deity within a gap in that which is understood with the
ever-expanding body of scientific knowledge, the danger being that science has
tended to fill its gaps, which then falsifies the god that was supposed to be
found there. The gods were once identified with the planets and indeed with all
sorts of forces or powers which were eventually naturalized. Modern
naturalism has thus pushed the gods not just out of our solar system but out of
the whole known universe. Darwin even showed how species could naturally
evolve without any intelligent designer. All that’s left for the theist,
philosophically speaking, is some unknowable, transcendent, supernatural First
Cause which is removed from nature, which isn’t personal, and which therefore
isn’t the theist’s God at all. In line with mysticism, reason doesn’t
establish this source of nature so much as faith does, since this Source is
stipulated to be beyond our understanding.
In any case, the rational, science-centered, and indeed
subversive aspect of philosophy ensures the shakiness of philosophical theism.
This may seem to beg the question against theism, but the judgment here is
based on the historical induction which I’ve outlined above. The theist’s
synthesis of philosophy and religion is dubious at the outset, because the
theist has the audacity to attempt to turn her opponent’s weapon, being
philosophy, against the opponent. This is like saying that guns are best used
in support not of war but of peace. On the contrary, guns can’t help but break
the peace, because to use them is to commit acts of violence. Likewise,
philosophy can’t help but undermine socially useful beliefs and practices, such
as theism and religion, since to think philosophically is precisely to exercise
doubt, to ask deep questions, to demolish everything that’s taken for granted
and to rebuild only what passes the test of rigorous skepticism. Scientists
test their hypotheses with physical experiments, while philosophers test their
speculations and analyses by submitting them to the crucible of limitless
debate. The historical trend of Western philosophers’ skepticism and
subversion isn’t accidental. Western philosophy is defined by the ancient
Greek tradition, and the love of wisdom precludes an equal love of anything
else such as fame, happiness, or power. This means that philosophy is an
obsession with the truth, a dangerous love that disregards its personal and
social consequences. At best, the philosopher trusts that the rational search
for the ultimate truth will benefit the seeker rather than, say, derange her.
It was left for Sade and Nietzsche to point out that the death of God may prove
socially disastrous.
So is theism likely to be rational? To count as a
worthwhile explanation, it would have to increase our understanding to say that
a person created the universe. But the moment of Creation would have been
miraculous and thus inexplicable to us, and the notion of an entirely
immaterial mind runs counter to mountains of evidence. People as we understand
them have minds which depend on physical brains. Where, then, is God’s brain
supposed to be? If God has none, he’s not literally a person, in which case we
must shift from theism to some more esoteric conception, and we’re no longer
talking about philosophical theism. If God has personal qualities, they
should be just as in need of explanation as the qualities of natural persons
which the positing of God is supposed to explain. Again, if God’s qualities are
special in that instead of possessing them, for example, God is identical with
them, in which case God wouldn’t have love but would be love, God
wouldn’t be like any person on Earth. In that case, calling God “personal”
would be vacuous, since God’s thoughts and feelings would have nothing
to do with our kinds of mental states. A useful metaphor for X has to
shed light by including more similarities to than differences from X.
But the more similar God is to a human person, the less explanatory value
theism has, since in that case positing God commits the fallacy of special
pleading. We can’t explain how people came to be in general by saying they
all come from a special person that has roughly the same characteristics as
humans but that for some reason doesn’t himself require any explanation. Such a
pseudo-explanation may comfort the mob, but it doesn’t increase a philosopher’s
understanding. For reasons like these, theism fails as a rational
explanation. But since the stories that are central to theistic religions are poetic
myths, the notion that theism should be held to rational standards in the
first place is wrongheaded.
*****
Darwin Skeptic’s Opening Statement:
Why I think philosophy supports theism over atheism
Short answer: I think theism makes better sense of the fact
that we exist as free, spiritual, moral animals in a universe which exhibits
both beauty and design, and which also includes signs that the atheist can only
explain away as brute facts.
1. The Structure of the Cosmos
The universe seems very anthropomorphic in at least two ways.
One, the laws of nature are anthropic, in that they favor the existence of
entities that look very much like us (carbon-based intelligent life); a slight
deviation from the form of our laws and you have a boring, lifeless universe.
None of this was expected, and it came as a complete surprise (and shock) to
the first physicists who discovered it. The best move for the atheists
would probably be to posit some kind of multiverse. (But this has a host of
problems of its own, assuming of course a godless multiverse, that is,
fine-tuned metalaws necessary to produce universes. Another problem, as Paul
Davies argued, would be that our universe would most likely be a simulation,
and as such, our physics would be fake, which would be self-refuting to anyone
who wishes to argue for it from our physics.) Also, our universe has other
features which would have to be expected as brute facts, given the multiverse (e.g.
what we could describe as an over-the-top fine-tuning, low entropy state of the
early universe, which didn’t need to be tuned to such a high degree just to
allow for intelligent life). But a fine-tuned universe for life is not the only
thing to be expected, given theism (a premise granted by the atheist
cosmologist, Sean Carroll); it is also a very plausible assumption to grant
that if such a God existed, he would probably want his creatures to have some
knowledge about his existence and this is where evidence, such as the
low-entropy state of the universe would be one way of achieving such an end.
Second, the universe seems rigged in such a way that it is
user-friendly to our methods of inquiry; previous philosophers doubted
science's ability to discover laws governing the unobservable, and yet
scientists discovered precisely such laws using artificial, manmade
mathematical analogies.
2. The over-the-top power of human intelligence
We seem to have supernatural powers when we compare our
intellectual capability with other animals. We have this weird ability whereby
we can grasp the whole universe. As Davies put it:
One of the oddities of human intelligence is that its level of advancement seems like a case of overkill. While a modicum of intelligence does have a good survival value, it is far from clear how such qualities as the ability to do advanced mathematics . . . ever evolved by natural selection. These higher intellectual functions are a world away from survival ‘in the jungle’. . . Most biologists believe the . . . human brain has changed little over tens of thousands of years, which suggests that higher mental functions have lain largely dormant until recently. Yet if these functions were not explicitly manifested at the time they were selected, why were they selected? How can natural selection operate on a hidden ability? Attempts to explain this by supposing that, say, mathematical ability simply piggybacks on a more obvious useful trait are unconvincing in my view.
Our strength lies precisely in that which doesn't make sense,
given an evolutionary account:
Natural selection requires no understanding of quarks and black holes for our survival and multiplication. And yet, we find these expectations turned upon their heads. The most precise and reliable knowledge we have about anything in the Universe is of events in a binary star system more than 3000 light years from our planet and in the sub-atomic world of electrons and light rays, where it is accurate to better than nine decimal places. And curiously, our greatest uncertainties all relate to the local problems of understanding ourselves - human societies, human behaviour, and human minds - all the things that really mattered for human survival.
Of course this doesn’t mean that evolutionists couldn’t come
up with some possible explanation, but it seems to flow naturally from a
theistic picture of the world, especially if—as some monotheistic religions
hold—we were created in the image of God.
3. The applicability of mathematics (or unity of physics
and mathematics)
Throughout history, mathematicians have developed tools that
only much later came to serve a function in physics (e.g. Riemannian geometry).
In his classic, “The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics,” Wigner
regarded this fact as a “miracle” that we simply could not explain. Related to
the problem of human intelligence, Wigner said: “certainly it is hard to
believe that our reasoning power was brought, by Darwin's process of natural
selection, to the perfection which it seems to possess.”
Columbia University mathematician and physicist Peter Woit
wrote a new paper on this subject, called “Towards a Grand Unified Theory of
Mathematics and Physics,” in which he reviewed the development of mathematics since
Wigner’s time: “During the half-century since Wigner’s talk, the connections
between quantum field theory and mathematics that have come to light go far
beyond anything that Wigner could have even dreamed of…Wigner’s ‘unreasonable
effectiveness’ miracle is ultimately a claim that a unity of mathematics and
physics exists despite our lack of any good reason to expect it.”
I agree that there is little reason to expect such a unity,
given naturalism. But if there were a God who created the universe accordingly
to a plan, and if mathematical truth were grounded in the mind of God, we would
have reason to expect a unity of physics and mathematics. It seems a plausible
expectation, given theism.
4. Mathematical Platonism is more obviously a live option
on theism than on atheism
Most mathematicians are mathematical Platonists in practice.
(Many great mathematicians were explicitly so in writing too (Alain Connes);
that is, they act as if mathematical objects exist beyond time and space, but
when pressed they will reject such a view because, given naturalism, there is
no way for us to have knowledge of such a Platonic realm of abstract objects.) This
is not to say that pure Platonism doesn’t create complications for theism. But
nominalism seems false to me. When I think about mathematics, it seems to make
more sense to think of mathematical structures as being discovered rather than
invented, and this structure exists in a sense in the mind of God. The primary
reason naturalists rejected Platonism was because of the knowledge problem, but
this has rarely been raised as an objection, given theism; rather, it is raised
against Platonism on the assumption that theism is false.
5. Teleology in biology need not be a mistress, but she
can be your wife
This is again a similar situation to what we have in
mathematics. Virtually all biologists are teleologists in practice, since they use
teleological language when describing objects in biology. Virtually every sane
biologist agrees that things in biology look designed, and this is not an
aesthetic judgment, that is, something which looks less so once we zoom in.
It is the other way around in biology: from far, things seem simple and crude,
but once we zoom in we can see an exquisite design. Dawkins even defines
biology as “the study of complicated things that give the appearance of having
been designed for a purpose”. It seems that, given theism, this can be expected
and easily explained, whereas the naturalist is forced to argue that natural
selection is the Great Illusionist. This doesn’t necessarily mean that
naturalism is false, but again the burden is on the naturalist here. Given that,
to date, we have hardly a good explanation for explaining the origin of a
single protein via natural selection and random mutation (Darwin’s mechanism),
it seems we are a long way from settling this question (which I know most
atheists take for granted).
6. Beauty exhibited in the laws in nature
This one is very hard to explain away with many-universes
type explanations because it is not a necessary condition for life as far as we
can tell. There was no reason for the structure of the universe to exhibit
beauty in the form of mathematical simplicity, and yet physicists have
historically used this as a guide to truth. Paul Dirac, the atheistic quantum
physicist even went so far as to suggest that this was more important than
having your theory match experiment! It seems this would make sense if God
were an artist.
7. Moral realism less of a problem on theism than on
atheism
Again, a similar situation to what we have in both our
mathematical practice and biology. Everyone (well, almost everyone) acts as if
moral realism is true. Even atheists are outraged (perhaps more so than others)
by what they perceive as moral injustices. Everyone acts if we are all bound by
some moral standards that transcend purely human conventions. Most people think
the Holocaust would be wrong everywhere and always, even if the Germans had won
the war and persuaded everyone that it was good. This again seems easier to
explain, given theism, that is, if humans are beings with dignity created in
the image of God who therefore have moral worth.
8. The failure of reductionism
It seems to me that if naturalism were true, we should be
able to reduce everything ultimately to physics (since fundamentally there would
be nothing else), and yet it seems we are nowhere near achieving this. To date,
not even chemistry has been reduced to physics, biology is nowhere near being
reduced to chemistry, and this is what one should expect if Mind were more
fundamental than matter.
9. Problems in the philosophy of mind are less acute,
given theism
Most of the unsolved problems in the philosophy of mind,
such as the problems of consciousness and intentionality, the mind-body
problem, and the problem of free will are less severe, given theism, because in
theism there are more live options for a consistent philosophy of mind. (This
is why you will find few theists have argued against the existence of mental
objects or freedom of the will, whereas you don’t have to go far to find
atheists who deny the existence of such.) For instance, given theism, it is
plausible to hold to some form of dualism (be this property dualism or, God
forbid, Cartesian dualism) or some form of hylomorphism, whereas given
naturalism, one is restricted to some form of eliminative materialism.
*****
Ben Cain’s First Reply:
Your opening statement points to several mysteries in
science and nature, and suggests that theism clears them up better than does
atheism. Unlike many naturalists, I actually agree with you that our species is
anomalous. However, theism doesn’t explain these mysteries well or better than
does philosophical naturalism. To the extent that theism seems to make sense
of otherwise perplexing facts, such as our species’ high intelligence or the
consensus about morality, that’s only because theism is unfalsifiable
and could be made compatible with any conceivable piece of evidence. So
theism is a pseudo-explanation and the rational superiority of theism is an
illusion.
Theism is the belief that a perfect person created and
intervenes in the world. Theism itself is thus exoteric, meaning it’s an
expression of our tendency to anthropomorphize whatever we attempt to
understand at the intuitive level. That doesn’t mean theism is thereby false,
since that would be the genetic fallacy. But it does mean that the theistic
notion of ultimate reality or of the source of everything in nature is dubious.
As a refinement of animism, theism is the result of a gradual
disenchantment of the world, as populations fled the wilderness and the life of
hunting and gathering and crowded into walled-off civilizations. This momentous
anthropological shift pushed spirits further and further away until the talk of
gods became vacuous and the gods themselves were vestiges, because we’d
forgotten what they really were. Spirits, angels, demons, faeries, goblins,
ghosts and gods are mental projections. They were the result of naive
attempts to ward off fear of the unknown, by humanizing everything in
experience.
Precisely because people once lacked godlike physical power
in nature, and were only several animal species in the same kingdom as all the
other animals, as opposed to reigning over the planet like we seem to do now,
our distant ancestors could only imagine that nature was tamed. And so
they envisioned that the world is an enormous society: the wind and the rain,
the day and the night could be negotiated with through prayer and rituals,
because everything was alive and mentally active. That way, the powerful human
talent for interpreting the contents of other human minds could be extended to
apply to whatever the ancestors encountered. Animists thus related to the world
much as all children instinctively do, since they regarded everything as imbued
with magical powers and mystery. They could hardly have done otherwise, since
those distant ancestors had no other advantage than their mental power, because
their technology was still primitive. Other animal species had greater speed or
strength, but we excelled in our ability to conceive of mental maps and to make
those maps especially relevant by grounding them in our experience. Thus, our
ancestors could mentally simulate possibilities and judge their worth by
applying familiar criteria such as the rules for social engagement.
In short, the animists didn’t sharply distinguish between
subjects and objects, and so they assumed that spirits were everywhere. That
made sense to the egalitarian, hunter-gatherer societies. Monotheists and
polytheists took those omnipresent spirits and packed them into fewer but
denser forms, as it were. They did so in response to two developments: the vast
increase in human power over nature, thanks at first to farming, and the rise
of great chieftains and kings, and of the more hierarchical nature of civilized
society. The more technological control we had, the less we needed to rely on
compromises with fickle spirits of the wild. And the remaining spirits had to
reflect the new kind of society to fulfill their function of comforting the
masses and providing for the meaning of their life. Thus, the spirits became gods
modeled on monarchical or aristocratic human rulers.
My point in submitting this commonplace account of the
origin and evolution of religion is that mysteries such as the natural order,
the unreasonable effectiveness of math, and the universality of moral judgments
are never explained by appealing directly to God; instead, their
mysteriousness can be neutralized by turning to the theistic mental
projections, to the humanizing filter we lay on top of what philosophers
think of more neutrally as the ultimate ground of Being. For example, your
opening statement says that the fine-tuning of the universe to allow for the
emergence of intelligent life is “expected” if we assume theism, but this
assumes in turn that we would have the foggiest notion of what an infinite,
eternal, supernatural person would want. It assumes the validity of some
divine revelation so that we could (vainly) affirm that God created the
universe primarily because God wanted to create us. But not every
creation myth is so self-serving and myopic. There have been hundreds of
creation myths, some of which treat humanity as a blip in cosmic history.
Hindus say the universe is sustained by Vishnu’s dream, and when he awakens one
of infinitely many cosmic cycles will end. Indeed, why wouldn’t God
create many different universes, including lifeless ones, if he lives forever?
Why wouldn’t God have already created all the universes of the
physicist’s multiverse? What else was God doing before the Big Bang? And so why
wouldn’t God’s plan be unfathomable to us? Clearly, the assumption that God
created this universe because he wanted intelligent life to evolve derives from
the same anthropocentrism that led the animists to socialize nature and the
early theists to pack spirits into king-like rulers whose existence would
thereby validate human civilizations.
One of your theistic arguments would have to be: (1) The
universe is mysterious for its tendency to support intelligent life; (2) God
would want to create such life, whereas atheists have to leave that cosmic
tendency unexplained; (3) the cosmic tendency makes more sense if God created
the universe than if there were no God; (4) therefore, philosophy supports
theism better than atheism. But (2) is dubious. Suppose there is a God but he
didn’t create our universe; instead, our universe popped into being, as in
quantum mechanics, and life evolved painstakingly and obviously by accident
over billions of years. In that case, a theist might say that this lack
of fine-tuning is likewise evidence of God’s handiwork, since God would want to
hide his role in creating the universe so that any life forms that happened to
evolve wouldn’t depend on God but would have to fend for themselves and become
strong and independent creatures. The possibilities of what a deity would
want are endless—not necessarily for the deity, but for us, because we
perceive through a glass darkly, to borrow Saint Paul’s expression; we are in
full control over how we imagine our gods to be, what scripture to write or how
to interpret it, and what religion to belong to.
In speaking of divinity in the theistic manner, we are
speaking only about ourselves, about our anthrophomorphic projections, our
societal structures and cultural preferences. Again, this has been
understood in the West since Xenophanes. The comparative mythologist Joseph
Campbell popularized this point with his distinction between the futile
metaphors we use to understand ultimate reality, and the mystical experience of
God as the oneness of being. To say that God would want to create life, because
this or that myth or creed says so is to get caught up with the anthropocentric
screen. The source of theism’s unfalsifiability is that we control
the metaphors and the interpretations, and thus we can ensure that our religion
or theistic model conforms to every conceivable state of affairs. Theism in
its exoteric aspect, which includes the metaphor of ultimate being’s
personhood, is a fiction in that the popular theistic ideas are mental
projections. And so theists can dictate their picture of God just as any human
author can decide what to include in her fictional story. Christianity is a
marvelous example of this subjectivity, since despite the utterly anti-American
implications of the New Testament, the intrinsic amorphousness of all theistic
deities permits Americans to interpret Jesus as blessing their every imperial
adventure, capitalistic idolatry, and racist and sexist bigotry, just as the
early Catholics had done in defense of their accidental, anti-Jesus empire.
There is no need, however, to concede premise (1), since
there’s no need merely to imagine a world in which life evolved
painstakingly and accidentally over billions of years. That is in fact how life
evolved in this universe, which means the universe is wildly hostile to life.
It’s true that if the initial parameters of the Big Bang had been only slightly
different, life as we know it wouldn’t have been possible. This doesn’t mean
that no unknown form of life could eventually have evolved in those vastly different
universes. After all, the development of those universes would have
corresponded to altogether different models and so we could only barely guess
at their endpoints. We don’t even know for certain the endpoint of our
universe, because of the surprises of dark matter and energy, so we certainly
aren’t entitled to say that even though it seems to have taken billions of
years for life accidentally to emerge here, no strange kind of life could ever
emerge in any other kind of universe.
Indeed, it made some sense to speak of the source of nature
as having us in mind, when we assumed the universe was no larger than our solar
system and the Earth was at its center, as it seemed from the ancients’ limited
vantage point. Now that we know the universe is vaster than we can fathom and
is hardly full of life, and that phenotypes did evolve partly due to the random
transmission of genes from one generation to the next, as selected by the
different environments—not to mention the many other accidents such as the
meteor impact which made Earth safe for mammals—it seems farfetched to maintain
that the cause of any apparent cosmic fine-tuning was likely the human-friendly
intentions of a deity. We don’t know that the emergence of life is bizarre,
because we don’t know that other kinds of life couldn’t evolve under very
different conditions. Moreover, this sort of theistic argument would
establish at best a God of the Gaps, since the fine-tuning is only currently
mysterious. Were naturalists to explain the fine-tuning, such as by further
justifying the multiverse theory, this reason for theism would disappear. And
as I said earlier, scientists have tended to fill their gaps.
Another problem is with (3), since as I said at the end of
my opening statement, theism isn’t a good explanation of anything. For
example, theists are guilty of special pleading on behalf of their deity. There’s
no increase of understanding in saying that intelligent life was allowed to
emerge, because the universe was created by an
intelligent life form. Theism doesn’t thereby explain the existence of
intelligent life at all, but only presupposes the existence of
intelligence, using our interpretation of it, as I said, as a magic top hat to
hide a rabbit or anything else we’d need to feel better about some situation in
which we find ourselves.
Similar points apply to your other proposed mysteries which
you think indicate theism, although each also calls for its own discussion.
I’ll have to turn to the others in later replies, but let’s look at the second
one, at our peculiarly high intelligence compared to that of other species. I
think natural selection is a red herring here, since the cognitive revolution
was due to cultural, not biological evolution. For example, the shift to
farming gave people the time and luxury to philosophize. Paul Davies is
mistaken: scientific reasoning could indeed piggyback on a more primitive and
useful trait, such as our talent, once again, for mind-reading, for managing
social relationships by supposing and interpreting intentions and social cues,
which is the talent that still attracts women to soap operas. Objective
reason developed from social reason. The transition between them was made
easier by animism and theism, which allowed early philosophers to think of the
world as partly social/spiritual and partly impersonal. In any case, once reason
was dedicated to achieving culturally-defined goals, reason was free to change
with the cultures. A humanistic revolution such as the one we find at the start
of our modern age would have coincided with progress in the independent use of
reason, which is just what happened, as I outlined in my opening statement.
In any case, once again we should banish anthropocentric
thoughts even while acknowledging our species’ strangeness; just because
we’re different doesn’t mean we’re better. Black holes are also anomalous
and they spell grim death for countless worlds. Likewise, our high intelligence
is narrow in scope. Science empowers us with technology, but doesn’t thereby
make us wiser or more ethical. On the contrary, the greater our control over
nature, the more self-serving our artificial environments and thus the more
vain and short-sighted we might become. This, too, is what happened in
technologically-advanced societies after the Industrial Revolution and the
creation of mass consumerism. So our high intelligence may allow us to
understand the universe, while it may also have a hand in our imminent
self-destruction. Those that would have the last laugh, after our demise by
war or ecological catastrophe would be the “dummy” animal species we tried to
enslave or exterminate that could then carry on for millions of years without
us, like the dinosaurs.
*****
Darwin Skeptic’s First Reply:
You say atheism is more rational than theism, as far as
philosophers are typically concerned. I suppose you are appealing to the
numbers of modern day philosophers. If so I agree, but again I think this comes
down to a host of issues—not so much that theism is untenable philosophically,
but that most philosophers probably prefer God’s nonexistence. Perhaps a
minority, granted, but as the atheist Quentin Smith pointed out, some of the
most prominent late philosophers are theists. The arguments against God's
existence are rather thin. It seems almost a default position to take for
granted that God doesn't exist in our day and age. I lost count of how many
times I read that Darwin or Hume settled this question in the negative, as far
as many if not most philosophers are concerned, which is indicative of the poor
shape of popular philosophy.
You say Western philosophy grew out of a rejection of
popular religion. I agree, but this was because such philosophers were able to
show successfully why those religions were absurd (which is where the analogy
breaks down with atheism); it is relatively easy to show that Zeus does not
cause lightning, but it is another thing to show why something exists instead
of nothing, or that cosmic or biological design is only an appearance. Yes
naturalism was there from the very beginning of Greek philosophy, but some
Greeks were not too far off from theism: the Pre-Socratic philosopher
Anaxagoras with his "Cosmic mind (Nous) ordering all things" came
very close to a monotheistic conception of God.
Granted, Plato and Aristotle's gods were very far from the
Christian God, but they were significant improvements over the polytheistic
gods that came before them. I would argue that they were closer, much closer to
the Christian conception of God compared to the natural gods which dominated
Athens in pre-Socratic times.
It is true that for Aristotle, his God had no direct role
with the teleology in nature, but it seems his justification for this was
largely based on questionable theological premises (it would be beneath his God
to get His hands dirty). This was perhaps a cultural projection on his God,
since ancient Greek philosophers would look down on manual labor; the dignity
of manual labor was a foreign concept.
You say Socrates became a secular Christ figure and died for
truths of naturalism and atheism. But as far as I know he was a polytheist;
some of our earliest recorded teleological arguments for intelligent design go
back to Socrates.
I'm not sure I grant your explanation for the so-called
"dark ages." This is a misnomer according to the vast majority of
historians. The Roman Empire collapsed by itself due to internal problems, so
this had nothing to do with Christianity. And yes, there were some Christian
figures who were opposed to all things pagan, but this was a minority position,
since the early Christians were quick to defend Greek philosophy on theological
grounds. As Clement of Alexandria put it: “We shall not err in alleging that all things necessary
and profitable for life came to us from God, and that philosophy more
especially was given to the Greeks, as a covenant peculiar to them — being, as
it is, a stepping-stone to the philosophy which is according to Christ.”
Or as Edward Grant put it: “With the total triumph of
Christianity at the end of the fourth century, the Church might have reacted
against pagan learning in general, and Greek philosophy in particular, finding
much in the latter that was unacceptable or perhaps even offensive. They might
have launched a major effort to suppress pagan learning as a danger to the
Church and its doctrines. But they did not” (The Foundations of
Modern Science in the Middle Ages, 1996, p. 4).
Consider Boethius, the 6th century Christian who wrote Consolation
of Philosophy, which was to become one of the most celebrated and influential
works in the Middle Ages. Yes, the Church did many things which were
wrong, and yes, they condemned teachings of Aristotle, but the Church was also
largely responsible for the promotion of much of his work. Aristotle’s physics
dominated Europe in large part because of the Church. Christians were his
earliest serious critics, starting in the 6th century, and later in the 13th;
interestingly, these Christians appealed to Christian scripture when
challenging Aristotle.
You say that when more ancient texts became available in the
Medieval Period, this sparked the development of modern science and secular
philosophy, which fueled modern liberalism. One has to wonder where these texts
came from. Human liberalism did not start because of ancient texts, since
things such as human infanticide and slavery were perfectly rational in the
ancient world; it was only with the rise of Christianity that such practices
became taboo, because Christianity had such an over-the-top view of man. At the
heart of classical dynamics lies inertia (Newton’s first law), the seeds of
which can be traced back as far as the 6th century when the Christian
theologian John Philoponus criticized Aristotle on motion, and later again when
Buridan would justify his impetus theory by explicitly appealing to Genesis.
The same goes for Galileo’s crowning achievement, as Clifford Truesdell put it:
The now published sources prove to us, beyond contention, that the main kinematical properties of uniformly accelerated motions, still attributed to Galileo by the physics texts, were discovered and proved by [14th century] scholars of Merton college....In principle, the qualities of Greek physics were replaced, at least for motions, by the numerical quantities that have ruled Western science ever since. The work was quickly diffused into France, Italy, and other parts of Europe. Almost immediately, Giovanni di Casale and Nicole Oresme found how to represent the results by geometrical graphs, introducing the connection between geometry and the physical world that became a second characteristic habit of Western thought...
Again, you referenced Hypatia and Bruno, who are usually
portrayed as martyrs for science, but historians have pointed out that this is
largely based on myth. Hypatia got herself involved in politics, but some of
her biggest fans were Christians who spoke very highly of her, such as her most
ardent student, Bishop Synesius. Bruno was a prophet for Hermeticism, and his
support for heliocentrism was based on religion not science.
Free thinking for Newton or Leibniz never led them anywhere
near atheism.
You say that early modern intellectuals argued for esoteric
theism (which wasn’t popular with religion), and yet Newton argued for the
existence of a God that also had to intervene in the natural world to prevent
our solar system from collapsing in on itself (after he determined that our
solar system was unstable). Both Newton and Kepler were driven by explicit
religious agendas; Newton stated himself that he hoped for nothing more than to
persuade his readers of the existence of a Deity. This was his aim in writing
his Principia.
An irony of course would be that Newton’s success would lead
to the rise of Newtonianism, which is ironically something that Newton would
reject, but I digress.
As for God being chased out of the planets, Genesis in
opposing Babylonian and Egyptian creation myths certainly does chase out the
living souls from these objects by treating these and every other celestial
object as ordinary physical objects created by God. (This arguably kicks off
the grand project of disenchanting nature, ultimately leading up all the way to
the mechanistic philosophy which would ironically come back to haunt
Christianity as its own Frankenstein monster.) But this was hardly the fault of
“free-thinking atheism.”
As far as Kepler was concerned, he found God in the planets
with his laws of planetary motion. (This is a hotly debated topic among
philosophers of science, since Nancy Cartwright argues that the concept of laws
as traditionally understood simply has to be abandoned since there is no God).
It is not at all clear how God just became less relevant with the progress of
time. Fast forward to today and these problems have only grown worse, since
today we have the fine-tuning problem, etc. Gaps do not seem to go away and
progress in science seems to expose new gaps.
You keep talking about the mob. Jesus was killed by the mob.
I agree with you that the mob is bad, but the growing mob of 2017 believers isn’t
made up of believers in the monotheistic God! (Unless of course we are talking
about the Muslim world, but I am referring to the West).
The claim by the modern Crowd of believers is that Darwin
explained how species can evolve naturally, but as many prominent evolutionists
would tell you, this issue is complicated. At best, Darwin’s theory works at
its proper scope of applicability: explaining minor changes of pre-existing
component parts. But Darwin’s theory does not touch on the issue of innovation
or higher taxa change. Of course, most evolutionists assume that species-level
micro changes can simply be extrapolated to explain higher taxa macro changes,
but this would be the equivalent of physicists who thought that Newton’s laws are
applicable at relativistic speeds and high gravitational fields or that GR was
applicable to singularities like those at the center of black holes. As one
evolutionist put it:
Athough, at the phenotypic level,...[evolutionary theory] deals with the modification of existing parts, the theory is intended to explain neither the origin of parts, nor morphological organization, nor innovation. In the neo-Darwinian world the motive factor for morphological change is natural selection, which can account for the modification and loss of parts. But selection has no innovative capacity: it eliminates or maintains what exists. The generative and the ordering aspects of morphological evolution are thus absent from evolutionary theory. (Gerd B. Muller, Homology: The Evolution of Morphological Organization (MIT press, 2003))
Admissions such as these are pervasive in the literature.
Even if I had to grant that evolution or a similar theory had successfully
explained away the appearance of design, this would still not rule out actual
design, as these Dutch philosophers point out in their paper, “Design Hypotheses
Behave Like Skeptical Hypotheses”:
It is often claimed that, as a result of scientific progress, we now know that the natural world displays no design. Although we have no interest in defending design hypotheses, we will argue that establishing claims to the effect that we know the denials of design hypotheses is more difficult than it seems. We do so by issuing two skeptical challenges to design-deniers. The first challenge draws inspiration from radical skepticism and shows how design claims are at least as compelling as radical skeptical scenarios in undermining knowledge claims, and in fact probably more so. The second challenge takes its cue from skeptical theism and shows how we are typically not in an epistemic position to rule out design.
Skepticism always goes both ways. I do agree with you that
the Crowd is untruth (as Soren Kierkegaard would put it), and I do agree with
you that philosophy tends to undermine cherished beliefs, but I think the
cherished beliefs today are naturalism, liberalism, and humanism in our day and
age (at least in the developed world).
*****
Ben Cain’s Second Reply:
I’m going to give you the last word on some of the details
from your first reply. But before turning to the rest of your opening statement
(I’m a little behind!), I’ll make some brief points here (I’ll come back to
your first reply in my third one). Your discussion of the Dark Age sets fire to
a strawman, because I never spoke of the Middle Ages as “dark.” On the
contrary, I said the torch of ancient philosophy was passed to some of the
Scholastics. I agree with what Hecht says in Doubt: A History, that the
reason the Medieval Church accepted ancient philosophy for so long was because
it had only scraps of it and didn’t understand the implications of those
scraps: “after Aristotle had been used as a textbook for centuries it was just
beginning to dawn on Europeans that Aristotle and the other ancient writers
were not exactly the early texts of the Schoolmen’s own, European civilization.
With astonishment, it was slowly being recognized that Aristotle and Plato and
the rest of them belonged to a fully other civilization that had its own
answers to the big questions and that explicitly rejected a God like Jesus”
(260). Then again, to say that anti-paganism was a “minority position” in the
Church is strange, since Theodosius I outlawed pagan religion and the Catholic
empire demolished pagan temples, destroyed part of the Library of Alexandria,
and persecuted pagans as heretics. In any case, I’m happy to agree that modern
humanism derived from a synthesis of ancient philosophy and certain
Judeo-Christian values. Indeed, this is the basis of the Nietzschean criticism
of liberalism.
In line with what I say in my first reply, I’d agree also
that monotheism helped push God out of nature; as I put it, the animist’s
spirits were packed into fewer but denser forms. But the point is that atheism
is the result, not the cause of how religion developed. I said
Hypatia and Bruno died for freedom of thought, not for science. I think there’s
some confusion about what I mean by “esoteric theism” when, for example, I say
that early moderns like Newton were esoteric theists. I mean their theism was
philosophical and thus subversive, unorthodox, and bordering on atheism. Newton,
for example, was an occultist (an alchemist and wannabe prophet). I’ll say more
about biology below, but I think there’s a strawman here too: as far as I know,
no biologist says natural selection is the only mechanism at work in the
natural creation of species. The atheistic point, though, is that the theist
fails to meet her burden of proof, because theism is no longer the only way of
understanding the apparent design of organisms. That is, there’s less of a need
for the God hypothesis, because at least one mindless creative process (natural
selection) evidently can do much of the work of an intelligent designer. I do
indeed say a lot about crowds, and there’s another odious one besides the
militant Islamists: the anti-intellectual, bigoted Americans who support Donald
Trump. In my view, the most important part of your first reply is your last
paragraph. I think we should focus on your point that secular humanists form a
low-ranking herd in the Platonic or Nietzschean sense, since we actually agree
to some extent about that, but I’ll have to return to it in the next reply.
Now back to your opening statement. Regarding the
mysterious applicability of mathematics to nature, I believe Unger and
Smolin have solved this mystery in The Singular Universe and the Reality of
Time. Smolin points out that the choice between thinking of mathematical
objects as discovered or invented is a false one. Something can have rigid
properties without having prior existence, as in the case of moves in a game
such as chess. Smolin calls such systems “evoked.” Once the rules of a game are
codified, there are objective facts about how the game is played, and there may
even be infinite discoveries to be made within the game, involving, for
example, comparisons of grand masters’ strategies. But contrary to Platonism,
there is no timeless, pre-existing realm containing all the truths of chess.
Mathematics may be evoked like chess, and the reason math would be so useful in
physics is that math developed as a way of summarizing our exploration of
nature.
As Smolin writes, “While an infinite number of mathematical
objects might potentially be evoked, the small and finite number that do prove
interesting—even on purely mathematical grounds—develop a very small number of
core concepts. These core concepts are not arbitrary—they are elaborations of
structures which are discovered during the study of nature.” The four core
mathematical concepts are number, geometry, algebra and logic, and they “each
capture a key aspect of the world and our interaction with it” (430). And so
while it is surprising that internal developments within math can apply to
nature, this would be no more miraculous than an internal development within
the game of chess applying to strategies in real warfare, or than such a
development in the Star Wars franchise applying to politics, or than one from
the Survivor reality TV show applying to real Machiavellian relationships.
Mathematics is perhaps the ur-game, since it’s been worked on for millennia by
people all over the world, so it’s much more powerful and refined than the
others. But all such games are connected to the real world from the outset,
because they’re evoked to model parts of nature. Thus, the miraculous
correspondence of math and nature is illusory, because as Smolin says, there’s
no such correspondence between nature and the totality of possible
mathematical relations and objects that could be evoked. The relevant parts of
math are preselected by our past observations which gave rise to the core
concepts.
In any case, the link between theism and the success of
mathematics or of the rational enterprise generally is weak. Again, theism
is unfalsifiable. If the nature of reality were made obvious to us, given
our powers of reasoning, the theist would say God made it obvious because he
didn’t want to confuse us or tax our mental faculties. And if we could never
understand reality itself, but only simplified versions of it that fit with our
intuitions which evolved for more mundane purposes, the theist could still say
God made it so, because God uses the left-over mystery to fire our imagination.
The latter is closer to the facts than is the former, which is as we’d expect
if human reason were an accidental product of biological and cultural
evolution: sometimes we’d figure things out, as in Presocratic philosophy
seeing through the charade of popular religion, and other times the real world
would baffle us, as in quantum mechanics or dark energy.
Regarding Platonism, the emotional consensus of
mathematicians has no logical bearing on whether abstract objects exist outside
the mind. Mathematicians get carried away with their game, just like musicians
who posit muses that feed them pre-existing melodies, or indeed like prophets
who posit angels that feed them the alleged Word of God. Playing a game well
may require nonrational inspiration, because if you overanalyze the art form
you may lose your ability to excel at it, as in tennis or golf or Woody Allen’s
character who overanalyzes the game of human life and who thus loses out in
various social competitions. In any case, the issue isn’t the possibility of
an abstract domain, but of a value-laden, teleological one. An atheist has
no problem admitting the possibility of abstract dimensions. Indeed, matter
isn’t what we think it is by way of commonsense intuitions: atoms aren’t chunks
of stuff at the most basic level. The more controversial point of Platonism is
that the abstract Forms are better than material particulars or copies
of the Forms, because the Forms are metaphysically closer to The Good, which is
the source of all being. Indeed, even that aspect of Platonism is strictly
consistent with atheism, because Goodness replaces God, but free-floating
goodness is strange and would invite a theistic pseudo-explanation. So a modern
naturalist would prefer to eliminate teleology and morality from theories of
fundamental reality, because the naturalist is interested in real explanations,
not fake ones that beg the question such as theism.
Regarding the beauty of natural laws, I don’t think
the grandeur of the universe implies theism. Things that emerge in nature have
aesthetic dimensions because they’re created—by mindless natural processes
which we can observe. Males who make up the vast majority of physicists,
mathematicians, and engineers prefer a visual kind of beauty because they
evolved to appreciate a female body type that indicates her health and
fertility. As Smolin points out, they’re misled in preferring simplicity in
their equations, since simple equations tend to be wrong and replaced by more
complicated expressions (429). The older, simpler statements may serve as
approximations, but the ceteris paribus caveat has to be removed for the
model to apply to nature in its complicated interconnectedness. Moreover, if
we’re talking just about the beauty of natural laws, which are only
simplifications and models, and not about nature itself, that beauty is only
skin deep. Just as we’re attracted literally to certain skin-deep forms in men
and women, but are repulsed by the blood-and-guts reality underneath the skin,
so too scientists may admire the elegance of certain arguments while they
ignore the brutal reality of European imperialism and economic inequality which
sustained the luxury that allowed for such scientific activities.
Regarding teleology in biology, I take the Darwinian
point to be that the systematic assembly of organisms is real, as is the
function of their traits, but that the organic forms and functions are
naturally rather than intelligently selected. Nature builds organisms by
several processes, without any design or plan. The environment, genes, and
behaviour of body types come together over time to adapt species, to hone their
traits, and to eliminate those that aren’t fit to live in new environments
which themselves change such as during ice ages. The point is roughly
Spinoza’s, which is that for all explanatory purposes, God is nature. There’s
no need to invoke an intelligent designer, since a mindless assembler will do,
as Darwin and modern biologists demonstrate with the magisterial power of their
theory. Moreover, as I said, appealing to a designer has no rational advantage,
since theism could only be a pseudo-explanation which begs the question. No
one explains life just by positing yet more life, that is, by positing an
intelligent designer. If we’re going to arrive at a primitive, basic
fact in our explanation, we can stop at the evident creativity of natural
processes; again, there’s no need for the God hypothesis. Regarding the origin
of proteins, of course natural selection doesn’t explain that, since Darwin’s
theory takes the origin of life for granted and applies only to its change of
form. The origin of life is still not well understood by anyone; again, saying
God, a living thing, created life—by an unfathomable miracle, no less—explains
nothing. But proteins do evolve and biologists can even measure the
different rates of evolution for different proteins.
Our universal moral judgments can be explained by our
common cooperative instincts and life cycle which give rise to similar
upbringings and formative experiences. Moral realism only confuses the issue,
since “moral fact” is oxymoronic. Facts are what they are regardless of how
they’re valued, whereas morals are essentially good or bad and thus valued.
Applying rational criteria to the poetic myths of religion amounts to a
category error, and it’s likewise wrongheaded to speak of objective facts of
morality. In any case, our moral judgments aren’t so universal, since they
depend on perspective and context. You say the Holocaust would be judged wrong
even if the Nazis won the war and tried to convince people the Jews deserved to
die. Yet Christians long for the coming of the Kingdom of God, which is the
rule of a tyrannical overlord who will sentence most people who ever lived to
everlasting torment in hell. That piece of theology should strike us as
obscene, because it fosters a grotesque mindset, but Christians believe hell
must be morally justified because God’s judgment is perfect.
I think it’s just a non sequitur to say that
naturalism entails perfect reductionism. Smolin’s cosmology, in
which time is objectively real and not just an illusion, is an example of an
atheistic account of nature which allows for the emergence of novel properties.
Spinoza’s and Schopenhauer’s metaphysics are other examples. You’re beating up
on a strawman if you think an atheist has to say that we should be able to
perfectly understand nature (see Lovecraft’s cosmicism) or that nothing
genuinely new can be naturally produced.
I don’t see how theism helps with problems in the
philosophy of mind. If anything, theism would make them worse in the manner
I’ve already suggested. Cartesian dualism has political utility, but since that
which would separate mind from matter would be miraculous divine fiat, there’s
no cognitive benefit of that proposition, meaning that it doesn’t improve our
understanding of the world. Consciousness and intentionality would still be
mysterious if God is the ultimate reality, since God would have those very same
properties and so they’d be left perfectly mysterious. Again, we need to
distinguish between social or emotional advantages and philosophical ones.
Theism helps to hold at bay certain unpleasant existential problems, such as
the fact of our personal death, but it doesn’t increase our knowledge—now
that we’ve recovered a good idea of what knowledge and philosophy really are,
in our secular Age of Reason.
None of this is to say that some of these mysteries or
anomalies, such as consciousness, morality, free will, and our godlike power
through technoscience pose no challenge to secular humanism or to new atheism.
I’ve argued on my blog that they are in fact challenging and they should push
us to an existential reckoning, as Nietzsche and the other existentialists
maintained. But it’s a bridge too far to say that these mysteries should push
us instead to theism. That seems to be our main disagreement. We agree on your
main assumption, if not on all your examples, but we disagree about the
conclusion that should be drawn. For you it’s theism, but for me it’s a
combination of existentialism, cosmicism, and pantheism. I think it would be
fruitful for us to focus on that disagreement and on the problems with liberal
secular humanism and new atheism.
*****
Darwin Skeptic’s Second Reply:
Hecht's explanation seems stretched. Would a more plausible
explanation not be that the Church decided to pick the Greek philosophers whom
they liked or whose thought seemed to be more compatible with Christian
theology (i.e. Plato and Aristotle), and incorporated this into Church doctrine
to the exclusion of others? As one physicist put it, “Among the Greeks, many
different beliefs were held by different philosophers, whereas the Hebrew and
Christian belief in the orderly creation of the world by God was century by
century hammered into the European mind to the exclusion of all other beliefs
until in the High Middle Ages it provided the fertile ground for the birth of
modern science” (P. E. Hodgson, Theology and Modern Physics).
I'm not sure that outlawing pagan religion is the same thing
as opposing Greek philosophy. There were Christian theologians who opposed
Greek philosophy, but this was a minority position. To quote another authority
on the subject,
[T]he logical tools developed within Greek philosophy proved indispensible. Furthermore, aspects of Platonic philosophy seemed to correlate nicely with, and therefore support Christian teaching…Thus in the second and third centuries we find a series of Christian apologists putting Greek philosophy, especially Platonism, to good use...[A] more typical attitude was that of Augustine…, another north African, who accepted Greek philosophy as a useful, if not perfectly reliable, instrument. Philosophy, in Augustine's influential view, was to be the handmaiden of religion—not to be stamped out, but to be cultivated, disciplined, put to use….And in his own works, including his theological works, Augustine displayed a sophisticated knowledge of Greek natural philosophy (David C. Lindberg, The Beginnings of Western Science, 600 B.C. to A.D. 1450, 1992, p. 150)
The Library of Alexandria as being destroyed by
science-hating Christians is one of the great myths recycled by ideological
neo-atheists, but neutral scholars have showed that this is again complete
nonsense.
By crushing animism and the Church persecuting Hermeticism, Christianity
in some sense might have fueled belief in atheism. Sure.
Having said that, non-teleological theories of evolution,
which were equivalent in substance to theories such as Darwin's theory of
natural selection were around before and during Aristotle's time. Much of his
project in biology (affirming genuine teleology) can be said to have been in
opposition to these theories of evolution, so atheists were clearly around (at
least in Greece) during the height of animism.
Hypatia did not die for her philosophical or religious views;
she was even a monotheist (at least, for the era, she believed in "The ONE.")
You couldn't get Newton more wrong. He invoked the
intervention of God as a scientific solution to the instability problem of the
solar system, he rejected the Trinity as traditionally understood, and he
denied the deity of Christ. But he was skeptical of secondary causes as being
sufficient to explain all of creation. He even denied that gravity can explain
the initial arrangement of the celestial bodies. Newton was an alchemist, sure;
he was a weirdo, but he was not a deist.
I am aware that evolutionists invoke all sorts of
mechanisms. But the consensus among "selectionists" (of the Dennett
or Dawkins type) is that NS does the heavy lifting, and this is the majority
position to this day. However, this is questioned by leading biologists
(Kauffmann, Newman, Shapiro, among others). One need not be a creationist or an
ID-advocate to see that the theory has serious limitations. The masses for the
most part—especially neo-atheists, but many religious folk too, such as
Biologos peeps, Catholics, etc.—simply take it for granted that Darwin
basically got it right.
Given that Darwin's goal was to explain away the appearance
of design as illusory, and given that our current champion for Darwin defines
biology as the “study of complicated things which give the appearance of having
been designed,” I am going to say the burden is on the Darwinist to demonstrate
that it is. Darwin never came close to explaining the origin of species as the
result of purely undirected processes. In reality he gave us a string of
theological arguments[1] (he invoked the problem of evil as a way to rule out
design from the start); he used human breeding as an analogy for natural
selection, which scholars have shown was atrocious as an analogy[2]; he didn't
understand genetics, and he erected a gigantic wall with which to protect his
theory, whereby he pushed the burden back onto the skeptic. As the philosopher
Robert Koons put it,
How could it be proved that something could not possibly have been formed by a process specified no more fully than as a process of ‘numerous, successive, slight modifications’? And why should the critic have to prove any such thing? The burden is on Darwin and his defenders to demonstrate that at least some complex organs we find in nature really can possibly be formed in this way, that is, by some specific, fully articulated series of slight modifications.
References:
[1] Charles Darwin's use of theology in the Origin of
Species
[2] Darwin and his pigeons. The analogy between artificial
and natural selection revisited.
*****
Darwin Skeptic’s Third Reply:
Smolin's criticism misses the mark because we are not
talking about a correspondence between the totality of maths and nature,
but rather about a very special subset of maths that required a very
advanced development of mathematics to fully appreciate. As Peter Woit put it,
“The lesson drawn here from history is that the fundamental laws of physics
point not to some randomly chosen mathematical structure, but to an
exceptionally special one, requiring a deep understanding of the
mathematical world in order to fully appreciate it.”
You say theism is unfalsifiable. I am baffled by that
statement. Problems with naive falsificationism aside, I don't think theism or
atheism is a scientific theory or even remotely as provable or disprovable as a
scientific theory.
Also, I don't see how theism is any less unfalsifiable than
atheism is. It is virtually impossible for God to demonstrate his existence by
inducing physical effects, in the way that, say, human intelligence can or
aliens could, since the atheist could simply expand his probabilistic resources
to the point where he has an infinite number of universes (in which literally
anything can happen).
An irony is that you have no issues with evolution theory
despite the fact that it is effectively impossible to show that some system could
not have been formed by some unguided (out of a potentially infinite number of)
processes.
Now you are saying it is ad
hoc, since if the universe were unintelligible, we could still say God made
it that way. The point is that most non-monotheistic cultures never took it for
granted that nature was intelligible, much less that it should be so to us.
Joseph Needham, in the end, gave this as his explanation for why modern science
did not take off in ancient China:
The de-personalization of God in ancient Chinese thought took place so early and went so far that the conception of a divine celestial lawgiver imposing ordinances on non-human Nature never developed...It was not that there was no order in Nature for the Chinese, but rather that it was not an order ordained by a rational personal being. Hence there was no conviction that rational personal beings would be able to spell out, in their lesser earthly languages, the divine code of laws which He had previously decreed.
Einstein also granted this point: “a priori, one should
expect the world to be chaotic, not to be grasped by thought in any way.”
It seems trivial only because we are living today when
science has come so far. But prior to the rise of modern science, none of this
was even thought possible; the Romans thought science was snake oil business,
whereas Christians on the other hand had a firm belief in the possibility of
science long before there was good reason to think so.
On naturalism, we are just a species of ape, no more significant
than any other, and nature is not obligated to make any sense to us, as the
philistine Neil deGrasse Tyson would put it. We are nothing in the grand scheme
of things on naturalism, and yet nature does
make a good deal of sense to us (to an insignificant species of ape). Again, this
is less surprising on theism than on atheism.
You brush off one of the most hotly-debated topics in the
philosophy of mathematics as something based on emotion. It seems as if emotion
is responsible for spawning all the alternative philosophies of mathematics,
because certain people are emotionally invested in naturalism:
Mathematical platonism has considerable philosophical significance. If the view is true, it will put great pressure on the physicalist idea that reality is exhausted by the physical. For platonism entails that reality extends far beyond the physical world and includes objects which aren't part of the causal and spatiotemporal order studied by the physical sciences. Mathematical platonism, if true, will also put great pressure on many naturalistic theories of knowledge. For there is little doubt that we possess mathematical knowledge. The truth of mathematical platonism would therefore establish that we have knowledge of abstract (and thus causally inefficacious) objects. This would be an important discovery, which many naturalistic theories of knowledge would struggle to accommodate.[1]
Your criticism of aesthetics I think also misses the mark.
On naturalism there is no reason to prefer one theory over another when they
are empirically equivalent, since each has a 50/50 chance of being true. But if
the universe is the work of a Divine Artist, then chances are that aesthetics
might be a good guide. This is also a great signature for God if he wanted us
to have knowledge of his existence, since this is very difficult to explain
away with multiverse- or anthropic-principle type explanations.
You say a designer of life would leave life unexplained, and
yet science always made progress by positing novel, unobservable entities
(Bolzmann's kinetic theory of heat, dark matter, etc.). We might as well argue
that such entities explained nothing unless we could explain or observe those
entities.
You say proteins do evolve and evolutionists can measure this.
The math doesn't add up very well: in one study, evolutionists concluded that
the number of evolutionary experiments required to evolve a simple protein was
10^70 trials [2] while another study concluded that the maximum number of
evolutionary experiments possible is only 10^43 [3]. Note that this number is
generous since they start off with a planet filled with bacteria, which as you
know is full of proteins.
With regard to morality, you are trying to give an account of
the epistemic problem of morality, but for me it is the ontology
of morality on naturalism that is the issue. We act as if morality is objective
and binding. For most of us, including atheists, this fact is no less obvious
than that we are aware of the fact that an external world exists.
I guess the point that I was trying to make was that
naturalism’s options are limited when it comes to the philosophy of mind, since
naturalism will most likely entail some form of eliminative physicalism, and
for physicalism consciousness and intentionality certainly pose a special
challenge. As Jerry Fodor put it, “[S]ome of the most pervasive properties of
minds seem so mysterious as to raise the Kantian-sounding question how a
materialistic psychology is even possible. Lots of mental states are conscious,
lots of mental states are intentional, and lots of mental processes are
rational, and the question does rather suggest itself how anything that
is material could be any of these.”
My beef is not with old atheism or with atheists who treat theism
as a live existential possibility; my beef is with the inconsistency and
overconfidence of the irrationally-happy neo-atheist.
References:
*****
Ben Cain’s Third Reply:
Although I still disagree with much of your discussion of
the details of how you think theism explains certain phenomena better than
naturalism (evolution, Platonism, beauty of nature, etc.), I’m going to focus
on your overall argument. This is because each of those nine issues is big
enough to merit its own long discussion, and if I’m right about the
unfalsifiability or explanatory emptiness of theism, there’s no need to go into
those details, because your conclusion wouldn’t follow. You suggest that the issue
of falsifiability is irrelevant, since theism isn’t being judged as scientific,
so you presumably have Popper’s falsifiability criterion in mind. But that’s
not my point. I grant that theism doesn’t have to be scientific to be true.
However, to be philosophical and not just dogmatic, theism must be
rational as opposed to purely faith-based. Therefore, philosophical theism must
adhere to the principles of critical thinking as these apply to arguments and
explanations.
Your entire argument for philosophical theism is that theism
makes sense of various phenomena, whereas the naturalist is supposed to
struggle with them. You’re saying, then, that theism tells us the cause (God’s
intelligent design) of certain facts (cosmic fine-tuning, utility of math and
Platonism, existence of consciousness and morality, and so on). You’re saying
theism increases the probability of these facts, whereas atheism makes them
unlikely. Specifically, you’re saying theism makes for a valid inference to
the best explanation of those facts. Therefore, your argument for theism
must include a valid case of abductive reasoning—not according to strict
scientific standards, but according to general rational ones.
One such standard is that an explanation must add to our
understanding, instead of piling one mystery on top of another; that is, a
rational explanation mustn’t be itself mystifying. Moreover, the explanation
must be a form of reasoning in the first place, not purely a work of fictional
art. That is, we must be dealing with intelligible propositions whose contents
aren’t entirely poetic, subjective, or vacuous. Also, a rational explanation
mustn’t be circular, meaning it must explain Y in terms of X, where X and Y
aren’t the same in relevant respects. So for philosophical theism to provide
the cause of cosmic fine-tuning and all the rest, it must first be a valid form
of causal reasoning. I’ve argued that it’s not and I’ve even explained why it’s
not and why we shouldn’t expect that it would be, because of how religion evolved
from anthropocentric mental projections in the animistic phase of
hunter-gatherers, and how its propositions function as poetic myths. Theism
doesn’t rationally explain anything; therefore, it doesn’t explain the several
facts (or alleged facts) you’ve raised. That’s my main counterargument.
Positing God as a cause doesn’t increase our
understanding, because God would be the biggest mystery and miracle of them
all. If you wish to counter this point by leaning on the anthropomorphic
metaphors, according to which God is rather like a human person, you’ll only
push the mystification back a step. This is because the literal conception of a
personal deity quickly becomes incoherent and thus, once again, empty of
explanatory content. For example, God’s mind would have no brain and his
thoughts and feelings would have to be sequential and temporally bound, whereas
God is supposed to be eternal; moreover, God would have to be perfect, whereas
there’s no such thing as a perfect human person, by definition, since the
meaning of person’s life is to struggle to overcome obstacles such as those
that arise from her internally divided nature (the older and newer evolutionary
layers of her brain). In other words, by our lights, a person is essentially
flawed and mortal, and so the notion of an immortal, perfect person makes no
sense. Notice, for example, how the New Testament’s portrayal of Jesus’
alleged perfection works by skipping over his adolescence so the reader doesn’t
have to wonder how Jesus overcame the awkward years of puberty and acting-out,
and how those formative years would have shaped his adulthood—as happens in the
case of every genuine person as opposed to a cardboard-cutout, fictional
character.
Theistic language is properly poetic and subjective, which
allows Christians, for example, to interpret their scripture in all sorts of
contrary ways. Is a scriptural passage meant to be taken literally or is it
metaphorical? Is it meant to be prophetic and to speak to everyone, even
millennia after it was written? Is it inerrant or did God only inspire the
human authors so that parts of the Bible are fallible, reflecting their
historical context? There are no objective criteria for settling such disputes
for theists, so they end up appealing to a Holy Spirit which supposedly guides
their interpretations, but this is a fancy way of admitting that biblical truth
is entirely subjective. In any case, poetic, subjective statements are
devoid of explanatory power, which is what I meant by calling theism
unfalsifiable. The point isn’t that theism is unscientific, but that
it’s rationally empty as a kind of talk about causal relations. You can
interpret God as the cause of anything, because God’s mind acts as a magic top
hat out of which you can pull a rabbit or a dove or whatever else you happen to
want. For example, you can say God intervenes in our life sometimes but not all
the time, and since God works in mysterious ways and it’s sinful to put God to
the test, there’s no way to predict when or how God will act. Sometimes,
according to conventional theistic wisdom, God answers our prayers by saying
“No,” but it would be futile for us to attempt to understand why God acts or
doesn’t act. That’s the whole point of the Book of Job.
By welding together the wildly-incompatible Old and New
Testaments, Christians ensured that their theism, in particular, would be
untestable, which is why their religion has been able to last for centuries.
The more foolhardy prophets who stood by their clear-cut declarations were
swiftly refuted by facts, and so their cults fell by the wayside. Only a
creed with primarily subjective content can be flexible enough to appeal to
anyone at any time, and thus only such a creed can serve a long-lasting global
religion. Similarly, so-called psychics like John Edward can claim to read
anyone’s mind on TV, by playing a sophisticated game of twenty questions with
the audience member (as explained hilariously in a South Park episode). The
audience member does all the work, so the psychic merely has to speak vaguely
enough at first, narrowing his statements as the member inadvertently reveals
more and more by her answers. It’s also how fortune cookies function: the
reader does all the work of applying the text to her life, because the text is
treated as poetry rather than as an objective statement of testable fact.
Subjective truth and emotional appeal have their advantages, of course; alas,
one such advantage isn’t that a work of art that functions in those ways can
serve as a rational explanation.
Finally, theism is obviously circular as an explanation
of anything to do with reason, meaning, design, or value, since God, the
purported cause of these phenomena, would himself have such properties, so it
would be like explaining the existence of trees by saying they all come from a
big tree. It’s actually a case of equivocation, since only most members of
a kind would thereby be explained by appealing to a special member of the same
kind. If we proceed to deny that that special member itself requires an explanation,
we’ve likely committed the fallacy of special pleading, as I’ve said in
previous responses. The theist can say God doesn’t have his properties but
somehow equals them, but that doesn’t work, as I’ve explained: again, it makes
the concept of God bewildering, and it equivocates on God’s personhood since
God would thus be quite unlike any human person.
You’ve said atheism would be just as unfalsifiable as
theism, since the atheist can always deny evidence of God’s existence. I agree
that atheism as a worldview may have an emotional core, which means the secular
worldview rests on a leap of faith, as William James said. Indeed, new atheists
such as Jerry Coyne and P.Z. Myers have disagreed on this question of whether
any empirical evidence would ever be decisive proof of God’s existence. For
example, if a five-mile high Jesus figure began walking the earth proclaiming
that God exists, atheists could maintain that this is the work of
extraterrestrials, as in the old Star Trek: Next Generation episode.
But again, we need to be more precise with our labels.
Atheism by itself isn’t a worldview and so the atheist has no positive burden
of proof. Atheism is just the denial of theism. The atheist’s substantive
worldview tends to be naturalistic. That worldview, then, is
well-supported by the success of science and its technological applications. So
philosophical naturalism is falsifiable; if science and technology stopped
working, we’d search for alternatives, although in that chaotic scenario we
wouldn’t likely be able to formulate doubts about science or to think at all.
Both theism (supernaturalism) and naturalism take natural order for granted,
but naturalism is the ontologically simpler explanation. Naturalism is also
more useful because it’s (at least imperfectly) reductive, whereas theism
explicitly adds confusion and even obfuscation. Like the notion of the elan
vital, or life force which biologists rejected as an explanation of organic
evolution, “God” is only a place-holder in search of a reference to an
understandable cause. Thus, the deeper reason why no empirical evidence of
God’s existence would suffice to convince a skeptic is that the meaning of
theism is never rendered precise enough to warrant rational inquiry into
evidence for theism in the first place. You either choose the theistic
mindset or lifestyle or you don’t, just as you either choose to like a poem or
a movie or a song or a food or a hat or you don’t.
You point out that some Eastern religions don’t take the
intelligibility of nature for granted. Christianity did, you say, and therefore
deserves credit for getting it right, since scientists have found order in
nature. But once again, Judeo-Christians can have it both ways since they can
interpret Genesis (or whatever) as saying that God created nature to be
understandable to humans, but they can also turn to Job if they want to say
that much of nature, including the existence of evil (unnecessary suffering),
is inexplicable to us; to the Fall of Adam and Eve, to allow for the limitation
of our cognitive faculties, as part of the strife their descendants would have
to suffer as punishment for original sin; to the numerous Christian
celebrations of miracles, if they want to say that the world isn’t entirely
natural, after all, contrary to scientists who are methodological naturalists;
or to Paul, who said that worldly wisdom is foolishness to God. Indeed, you’ve
appealed to abstract objects, consciousness, freewill, and morality as
phenomena which can’t be naturalistically or reductively explained, which is
why they supposedly call for a deus ex machina. But you also want to
give theism credit for predicting that the world could be scientifically
(naturalistically and reductively) explained. It seems your first fact in
your list of nine conflicts with several of the others in the list, such as the
fourth, fifth, seventh, eighth, and ninth.
But it’s strange to hold up Christianity as a beacon of
Reason compared to Eastern religions, since Hindu, Buddhist, Daoist, and
Confucian texts are far more rationally advanced and argumentative than
Christian ones. Many of the Eastern religions are themselves philosophical and
naturalistic. Medieval Christian rationalism amounted to copying Plato and
Aristotle, and the Age of Reason happened largely in spite of the Church, not
because of it, since the Church prohibited any method or statement which it
found to disagree with its dogmas. Moreover, not even scientists believe the
universe is necessarily intelligible to us. They subscribe to methodological
naturalism, which means their naturalism is only tentative and pragmatic; they
assume only that we might as well try to extend scientific reasoning as far as
it proves useful to do so. Therefore, naturalism and atheism are consistent
with there being parts of the world that will forever be counterintuitive to
us, such as the subatomic world or the Big Bang.
By contrast, if God made the universe primarily for us
(which is absurd now but wasn’t always so, since we now know the Earth isn’t
cosmically central and the universe is so enormous that we become insignificant
by comparison), there should be no reason for any gaps in our understanding,
nor should our prehistoric ancestors have needed the tens of thousands of years
for them to have struggled to understand the world, like the ignorant babes in
the woods they were evidently forced to be by the absence of any divine parent.
After all, humankind wasn’t born able to understand everything we’d have to
know to survive easily in nature. For many millennia, we clawed our way up
from ignorance, often dying prematurely because of our natural confusion and
because of the frugality of natural selection, which evidently built the
instincts that enabled us to endure. The haphazardness and gradualness of
human cognitive advancement is more simply explained by naturalism than by
theism. To the extent that the theist can make sense of both nature’s
partial intelligibility and incomprehensibility to us, the theist is only
making it up as she goes along, in which case theism should be judged as a
subjective work of story-telling, not as a rational explanation or argument.
*****
Darwin Skeptic’s Fourth Reply:
You claim that cosmic fine-tuning cannot support
philosophical theism in principle because “religion evolved from anthropocentric
mental projections.” Yet to be consistent, I would also have to reject modern
physics since its success was largely the result of “anthropocentric mental
projections” in the form of mathematical formalisms. But again, this is a
genetic fallacy.
You assert that positing God would not increase our
understanding because God would be the biggest miracle of all. Yet this only
begs the question because you presume that God’s mode of existence would or
could be no different from that of any being or object that exists in our
Lorentzian spacetime. You assume that God would exist as a caused cause,
actualized actualizer, or a moved mover (to borrow some Aristotelean jargon);
that she would exist as a composition (and thus require a designer) and exist
contingently (existing with the possibility of failing to exist), etc., in
which case it would be true that God’s existence would be miraculous. But this
is a straw god.
As for God providing no explanation, this doesn’t follow. By
your logic, an explanation would have an advantage even if the explanation were
false.
Suppose life was planted on earth by other life forms, and I
concluded that life on earth was designed because we happen to find the same
patterns in biology that we know are habitually associated with prior
intelligent activity (e.g. massive chunks of digital code in DNA). You object,
saying, “No, since unless you can explain where the aliens came from, you have
not explained anything.”
Or suppose I invoked a sculptor-of-the-gaps to explain
the familiar shapes on Easter Island. Applying your logic, the design skeptic
could conclude that his explanation was superior because he only needed to
invoke unguided natural causes, leaving no unexplained mysteries (such as the
whereabouts of the Islanders, their origin, why and where they vanished to, the
lack of evidence for their tools, etc.).
This doesn’t follow. Science gives explanations for things
all the time by postulating the existence of something novel which is itself
either not explained or unobservable.
Finally, there are no shortcuts in philosophy: you cannot
give yourself an epistemic advantage and claim your explanation is somehow
logically superior as a matter of principle simply because you produce some
effect free of charge.
I think you are stuck with this idea that “person = human
person,” but this is not at all what theistic personalists mean when they say
“God is a person.”
“Perfection” as it applies to God means something different.
I think there is a simpler explanation for why there is
little information in the Gospels of Jesus childhood. Most people started
talking about this Jesus guy, only after the crucifixion and resurrection;
people only then started to compile Gospels (it is not as though people were
writing Gospels and recording the words of Jesus in real-time). People did not
realize this obscure preacher from a small dusty village was actually God until
much later.
I agree the scriptures are complicated; the Bible is after
all a book written over thousands of years by more than 40 different authors.
It is an easier task, though, to see that certain books are of a certain genre
or vastly different from other books. Virtually all scholars agree that the
Gospels, for instance, were written as Greco-Roman biographies (with varying
levels of theological embellishment, to be sure, though Mark has less of that).
Again, saying that a transcendent God is our ultimate source
is not at all the same thing as saying that all trees came from a tree. Your
analogy would actually be a more accurate description of the atheist position,
since the atheist believes that ultimately we came from some physical object
that either always existed (as a brute fact, without explanation) or that
existed necessarily, i.e. that caused itself to exist.
You say that atheists have no burden of proof because “Atheism
is just the denial of theism.” This is again a nice semantic trick. I could
return the favor by simply redefining “theism” as nothing more than the denial
of the proposition, “God does not exist,” or of the proposition, “Nature is
complete.”
None of this actually settles anything.
Atheism most certainly is not merely a lack of belief in or a
denial of theism. Atheism is a commitment to a positive ontological status of
the universe. Atheism says something positive (and bold) regarding the mode of
existence of our universe; that is, that it exists necessarily or is
self-caused, or that it exists as a brute fact, and atheism adds other
positives such as that the order we see in it is merely apparent, etc. These
are all positive propositions. Theism can be defined as the lack of belief in
these positives.
Atheism is well supported by the success of science? Tell
that to Charles Peirce who doubted our ability to discover the laws of the
subatomic world, since evolution would have no reason or need to equip us with
the tools to do so. It is extremely ad hoc
to sit back now and declare that this success validates naturalism. This is
especially ironic, seeing that physicists relied on an anthropocentric strategy
(relying on mathematical formalisms designed for purposes of aesthetics and
convenience) in order to decode the workings of nature.
You say that both theism and naturalism take order for
granted, and yet science as a self-sustained enterprise only took off in
Western Europe when Christianity dominated the intellectual space. For
naturalism the order is merely an appearance; it is ultimately illusory.
You say I want to have my cake and eat it, since I want to
give Christianity credit for having the correct prediction as far as
intelligibility goes for the natural world; however, I switch to being a
skeptical theist when it comes to the problem of evil. I think this is a false dilemma.
If we posit God, I think we can see that some things follow logically
from that, especially for the natural world (that it would likely be rationally
constructed, for instance, etc.). I don’t think it follows, therefore, that we
should be able to know everything about God, though (exactly how he
constructed it, or why he allows evil, etc.).
I don’t think intelligibility entails complete reductionism.
Yes, monotheism inspired the first great unification of physics i.e.
terrestrial (physics) with celestial (astronomy) mechanics, but this idea
flowed from a rejection of Greek pantheism. The premise was that only
God was divine, meaning distinct from nature and not in the celestial realm,
and that therefore there was no distinction between terrestrial and celestial
matter. I don’t think it follows, therefore, that all unifications will or must
succeed. The driving forces pushing chemical evolution are obviously of a very
different sort.
I think you misunderstood my point on ancient China. I was
never trying to imply that they were somehow less sophisticated than Europe. The
scholar I quoted attributed nearly every single invention known to mankind to
China (not without criticism); he was very biased in his views on ancient
Chinese civilization. You said that theists were hijacking the success of
science after the fact, to which I was trying to make the point that the
assumption of the possibility of science was rare in the ancient world.
Christian Europe had a firm belief in the possibility of science, given their
metaphysics, whereas such a belief was lacking in ancient china:
“There was no confidence that the code of Nature’s
laws could be unveiled and read, because there was no assurance that a divine
being, even more rational than ourselves, had ever formulated such a code
capable of being read” (Joseph
Needham, The Grand Titration: Science and Society in East and West (Toronto:
University of Toronto Press, 1969).)
Haha, and no, Christian rationalism did not simply amount to
“copying Plato and Aristotle.” Christian physicists were brilliant also for
going beyond Aristotle and Plato, starting with John Philoponus planting the
first seeds for inertia already in the 6th century and with Aquinas for
pointing out where Plato made an error: “Plato strayed from the truth because
he believed the form of the thing known must necessarily be in the knower
exactly as it is in the thing known.”
The idea that the earth was cosmically central was actually
a product of Greek rationalism, since the ancient Greeks proposed that the
earth needed nothing below it; Anaximander postulated that the earth floated in
the center of infinity and was held in position because it is an equal distance
from all the other parts of the universe.
The fact that the universe is massive does not imply that we
are insignificant. To quote the French philosopher, “By space the
universe encompasses and swallows me up like an atom; [but] by thought I
comprehend the world.”
Also, we know why the universe is big, since it is a
function of its age. As Barrow explains,
This state of expansion means that the size of the Universe is inextricably entwined with its age. The reason that the Visible Universe is more than 13 billion light-years in size today is that it is more than 13 billion years old. A Universe that contained just one galaxy like our own Milky Way, with its 100 billion stars, each perhaps surrounded by planetary systems, might seem a reasonable economy if one were in the universal construction business. But such a universe, with more than a 100 billion fewer galaxies than our own, could have expanded for little more than a few months. It could have produced neither stars nor biological elements. It could contain no astronomers.
*****
Ben Cain’s Fourth Reply:
I can see how you might think the point about the origin of
anthropocentric theism in the ancient animistic mental projections commits the genetic
fallacy, but it’s more of an alternative inference to the best explanation.
Moreover, the point isn’t just genealogical, since I’m saying the current naïve
conception of God as human-like is also more easily understood as similar to
the ancient animist’s mental projection. So I’m saying the textbook notion of
God as a personal creator of the universe is more simply explained as resting
on anthropomorphic projections than on a real deity. I’m not saying theism is
false or dubious because of its origin; rather, I’m saying theism more likely
has one sort of origin (the deflationary one) than another (the naïve, literal
theistic one).
Your next point gets hung up on my use of “miracle” in my
saying that God would be “the biggest mystery and miracle of them all.” You
left out the mystery part, so you’ve missed the main point. The point is
that any deity worth worshipping must be essentially mystifying to us. If
we could understand what God really is, how he came to be or how he thinks, God
would be just another object, not the transcendent source and ground of all
particular things. I think you might agree with that. So the problem I’m
raising for the philosophical theist is that once you grant this more
subversive, mystical definition of God, you can no longer appeal to that
transcendent God by way of offering a rational explanation for anything. Philosophical
theism can’t help but objectify God, because reason is our main tool for
controlling things by understanding them, by carving them up into conceptual
boxes and analyzing the information for advantages and weaknesses.
What philosophical theism gains in a plausible concession
that God would have to be beyond our paltry metaphors—meaning that the
metaphors would misrepresent rather than provide partial truth (the partial
truth would be an idol, which is the main point of Judaism and perhaps Islam,
which Christianity contradicts)—it loses in the implication that philosophical
theism becomes equivalent to atheism: God, mystically defined, becomes
impersonal, an absolute emptiness (as in Buddhism) which is beyond all
objects and limited conceptions, and thus beyond the comparison with any sort
of mere person. And my point is that such a deity can’t be used in any rational
explanation, because it’s useless to explain something more understandable in
terms of something far less so. Remember also that my opening statement went
into this equivocation or pendulum swing between the mystical and the
literalistic notions of God.
So I’m not begging the question. Instead, I’m reducing
certain definitions of “God” to absurdity. I’m showing that the consequences of
defining “God” in certain ways don’t sit well with philosophy. The point of the
philosophical Absolute, as in Kant’s noumenon, is to recognize the end
of philosophy and the end of rational explanations. (Kant thought reason
“regulates” experience by leaping into such transcendent ideas, even though the
attempt to understand those ideas leads to incoherence.) The bottom line is
that while you say a mystifying or miraculous God would be a “straw God,” I’m
saying anything less than such an absolute, transcendent non-being or
non-object wouldn’t be God at all, but just one more being or object which
submits at least partially to our meager cognitive faculties. No such latter
deity would be worth worshipping, and so philosophical
theism misses the point of talking about God.
I agree that a partial explanation might be better
than none. But I’m saying the naïve notion of God as a personal being doesn’t
explain anything even partially, because that notion collapses into incoherence
or semantic emptiness. When you say God created the universe or designed life,
you’re saying nothing at all, upon analysis. So explaining the origin of
terrestrial life by positing a connection to life on another planet might be
useful as a partial explanation, even though it obviously wouldn’t count as an
explanation of life itself. That partial explanation would differ from theism
in that the former would make sense whereas the latter only mystifies and
obfuscates. Theism isn’t a partial explanation; instead, it’s a sort of
semantic fraud.
I agree that scientists explain some things by positing unobservable
causes. But there are at least two checks on those posits. First, the
unobservables must be understood to be natural entities as opposed to being
intrinsically mystifying like God or Spirit or any other poetic, unquantifiable
entity. As I said, any natural object or particular being, including a person
with one sort of character rather than another, wouldn’t be worth worshipping.
Second, the scientific explanation must have an objectively testable payoff,
not just a subjective, emotional one. Theism has the latter sort of payoff
which doesn’t count as good evidence for theism’s truth, since the fact that
theistic belief makes people happy can easily be explained in only
psychological terms which don’t require that God actually exist. Even if God
didn’t exist, we might have to invent God to feel better about the sadder,
godless alternative.
You say my main argument attempts to take a “shortcut” to an
“unfair” epistemic advantage. But there’s nothing unfair about my argument. All
I’m doing is analyzing the philosophical and the theistic sides of
“philosophical theism,” to show that your argument doesn’t even get off the
ground, which is why I don’t think we need to delve into the specifics of your
nine examples of things that theism supposedly explains better than naturalism.
I’m pointing out that a philosophical mindset has consequences. For example, it
obligates you to adhere to certain basic rational standards such as the ones I
outlined in my third reply. You’re the one who argued by appealing to the best
explanation and you’re the one who thinks theism can be supported by philosophy
rather than just by faith. All I’m doing is showing you the consequences of
thinking about God in that way. I’ve analyzed the terms (“rational explanation
by appealing to the best explanation” and the philosophical/mystical versus the
naïve, literalistic conceptions of God) and reduced them to absurdity for the
philosophical theist.
The reason I talked about human persons as central to
the naïve conception of God is that those are the only persons of whom we have
direct experience. You’re free to compare God to a chimpanzee or a dolphin or a
fictional alien such as E.T., if you like. Either way, to be a person is to fit
into a particular conceptual box. Persons have thoughts and feelings,
consciousness and free agency, a mind and a body. If you’re arguing for a
personal God in that sense, your concept of God will be incoherent and thus
won’t figure in a rational explanation of anything. That’s what I’ve argued. If
instead you think of God’s personhood as different from any familiar kind, I’d
say you’re equivocating on “person” and you should choose a different word to
refer to God’s identity, so there would be no temptation to misuse the familiar
word “person” when applied to something transcendent and therefore necessarily
impersonal (and unlike anything else in nature). The same goes for “perfect.”
Philosophers of religion typically define God’s perfection as a matter of
ramping up all his attributes to the maximum degree. So God is omniscient,
omnipotent, and omnipotent. He’s also immortal because he exists outside of
time, so he doesn’t change. And if you combine that perfection with personhood,
you naturally end up with contradictions and incoherence. Once again, then, we
shouldn’t attempt to rationally explain anything by appealing to such a
mystifying nothing.
Regarding the parody in which all trees are explained
as coming from a special tree, I notice that you respond to the parody by
switching to the mystical conception and speaking of “a transcendent God.”
Again, that’s the pendulum I expected to swing into action, from my opening
statement. In so far as God is a person (the naïve, exoteric, literalist
conception), God would have all the qualities the theist is supposed to explain
by appealing to God. Thus, my tree parody would hold. If instead God is
impersonal (the philosophical, mystical, esoteric conception), the tree parody
wouldn’t hold, since God would be no particular object of any kind and thus
nothing we even partially understand. In that case, your argument would still
collapse because the concept of your cause that supposedly explains various
facts throughout the universe would be empty, and your theistic explanation
wouldn’t adhere to rational standards of appeals to the best explanation.
Regarding the burden of proof, I said atheism has no positive
burden of proof. The burdens of proof here are unequal, just as they would be
in a debate about whether Mickey Mouse or leprechauns or unicorns exist. This
isn’t a semantic issue of redefining our views to be positive or negative, even
though I agree that denying that something exists has positive implications. If
leprechauns don’t exist, that means certain Irish individuals who try to lure
the creatures out of rainbows would be kidding themselves. So a-leprechaunism
would entail that the world is a certain way. Nevertheless, the person who
denies that there are leprechauns doesn’t have the same burden of proof as the
believer in leprechauns. It’s up to the person who claims to know how the
furniture of the world should be added to, to prove that that extra thing
exists. If I say there’s an invisible elephant standing next to you, do you
really think it’s up to you to disprove that assertion? And if the Church of
Invisible Elephants condemns your disbelief in such elephants and imprisons you
as an infidel, do you really think such a church would be remotely fair and
rational?
I know you think the concept of God is more useful than that
of an invisible elephant, but in either case it’s up to the believer to
demonstrate as much. The disbeliever has the burden only to evaluate the
believer’s case, to determine whether she should change her mind (although
the disbeliever is free to go beyond her epistemic burden and offer separate
negative arguments). And when you talk of the atheist as being positively
committed to a kind of ontology, you’re getting into a muddle I tried to free
you from by distinguishing between atheism and naturalism. Atheism has no such
commitments, since an atheist can say she doesn’t know what reality’s like
except that she knows God isn’t part of it. There need be no inconsistency
there. But atheists do tend to be naturalists, and yes, naturalism entails a
commitment to a certain ontology, and naturalism is independently
well-justified in the ways I said (science and technology work).
In saying that naturalism is justified, I don’t mean to say
that naturalism is complete or perfectly satisfying. On my blog I’ve argued
against a commonplace understanding of naturalism, and such cosmologies as
Hawking’s and Krauss’s, which attempt to show how a natural universe arises
from “nothing” are philosophically dubious, because these cosmologies
inevitably presuppose laws and equations which wouldn’t hold in a prior state
of absolute nothingness. Unfortunately, rational argument ends at some point,
so the ultimate question of where the universe came from may have to be decided
in an existential choice of what sort of person we want to be. We can take a
leap of faith in theism or in some reductive naturalism, or we can be agnostic
and ignore the question. That’s the Kierkegaardian level theists and atheists
should be arguing on, in my view, not from a pseudoscientific discourse of
appeals to the best explanation. Theism won’t fare well on philosophical
(non-existential) grounds.
Regarding theism’s unfalsifiability, I don’t think
you get out of the problem by saying our knowledge of God would be partial. The
problem is that there are no checks on what would be included in that partial
knowledge. That’s why there are thousands of contrary religions and sects:
you say we know X, Y, and Z about God, someone else says we know A, B, and C
about him, and there’s no common ground for deciding between the options. So
the problem is that the theist is always free to reinterpret the creed or
scripture to get out of an apparent difficulty, because her concept of God is
infinitely malleable. That sort of vague, poetic notion would be out of place
in a rational explanation; instead, such a notion clearly functions well in
emotional, social terms.
Your point that “Christian Europe had a firm belief in the
possibility of science given their metaphysics” is an interesting one. If it’s
true, it could be only an accident, not due to any predestination. Indeed, I
hardly think ancient Jews wandering in the desert had science in mind when they
worshipped one deity above all others. Instead, they meant to declare that
their ethical culture is superior to all other cultures. The main point of
monotheism is to be culturally exclusive. As Descartes showed with his
skeptical doubts, just because God created the world doesn’t mean we must be
able to understand what he created. Indeed, the Christian Gnostics themselves
said the creator God is evil and meant to beguile and imprison us in a lower
reality. And yet it may follow, as you say, that if God transcends nature, the
earth is united with the heavens, as the early modernists realized. But notice
that that requires taking the mystical side of the pendulum swing, which
practically entails atheism, not any kind of theism. If God is literally some
kind of person, he must be somewhere in the natural universe, in which case all
of outer space couldn’t be united with Earth. So I’d maintain that it’s the atheistic
implication of the philosophical, mystical conception of God which allows for
the possibility of science.
I don’t see how your point about the size and the age of the
universe helps you. The universe is ancient to allow for the natural evolution
of planets and living things. At best, that entails pantheism, not theism. And
the reason we’re insignificant, given that our planet isn’t cosmically central
or crucial, is that our values must be subjective and arbitrary rather than
grounded in ultimate reality. Our significance rests, then, entirely on our
fragile self-confidence, which flickers and fades as soon as we turn our
attention to the underlying absurdity of all life when life is viewed, as it
were, from the universe’s inhuman perspective.
*****
Darwin Skeptic’s Fifth Reply:
I think the reason why you go back to old inferences is
because you are trying to reduce all inferences to God as nothing more than an
argument from ignorance. But the mark of a good philosopher is to note key
distinctions, as David Snoke writes,
We must distinguish between bad explanations for certain things within the theistic world view, and arguments for the theistic world view itself. People arguing that comets were signs from God or that demons caused all sickness did not argue that God existed because comets and demons existed; rather, starting from belief in God, they posited a reasonable, though ultimately falsified, theory about comets and demons. In the same way, people working within an atheistic world view have proposed bad explanations for things, such as the theory of spontaneous generation or the Lamarkian theory of evolution. The falsification of a subtheory within a larger world view does not falsify the whole world view. If it did, every falsified scientific theory would cause everyone to reject all of Western science.
Compare a modern design inference with the argument that we
don’t understand magnets, ergo God:
(1) Crick’s sequence hypothesis (exact order of symbols
records the information) applies directly to genetic code and written text, and
so this is not an analogy
(2) Written text can always be traced back to an agent or
programmer, not an undirected process
(3) DNA software is best explained as the product of agency
(whether directly or indirectly)
OK, so you say that for God to be worthy of worship, it is
necessary that he remain mysterious. I’m not sure that this follows; for
instance, surely God could be more clearly revealed in the beautification in
the here-after. Would it follow that God would somehow be any less
worthy of worship?
Also, how much of God’s essence would actually be revealed,
say, if some patterns in nature continued to be resistant to materialistic
explanations and we found out that the reason for this is agent causation? Or
what if Plato was right, God used a demiurge and was thus not directly
responsible for the patterns we observe, but only indirectly so?
I think the central theorem of theism is arguably the notion
that God is the cause of everything that exists apart from him. So in a sense,
everything reveals something about God, since God is ultimately the Creator of
everything that exists. What follows from your reasoning is that God would not
be worthy of worship simply because we can observe the universe. But I think it
is almost the opposite: God is worthy of worship in part because we can
observe the universe; this is after all, a demonstration of his power.
Finally, we don’t really know fundamentally what human
intelligence is (we only know for instance what thinking is not, i.e.
computation, as demonstrated by Searle’s Chinese room, but not what it is), and
the fact that we can make design inferences in the case of prior human intelligent
activity (archaeology, forensics) or alien intelligence (SETI) would in no way
help fill this gap. So if the mystery concerning the essence of human
intelligence is conserved despite the fact that we can recognize the physical
effects induced by human intelligence, I see no reason why it should not hold
also for the effects induced by a transcendent intelligence.
You say you agree that partial explanations are better than
none. But this was not at all my point. My point was that, ultimately, all
explanations are incomplete, and ordinary design inferences no less so, but
no one would on such grounds consider them incoherent. There is nothing
incoherent in saying that Hitler wrote Mein Kampf even if you don’t have an
account of how Hitler’s ancestors (or the human race as a whole, or life) came
into existence. Similarly, we can infer design from patterns in nature (if they
warrant such inferences) even if we could not understand where God came from or
what God is.
You say the notion of God as a personal being doesn’t
explain anything. But God as a being with will and intellect would have
certain consequences. It would mean that such a being is capable of
communicating with us, and it could mean that such a being can move things to achieve
an end. For instance, God could actualize one tiny subset of laws out of the
whole set of possible laws because he intends for complex carbon based life
forms to exist. On theism, other universes with different laws don’t have to
exist, precisely because the conception of God is of a being with intellect and
will.
Luke Barnes uses the analogy of a burglar:
Naturalism is, in the terminology of probability theory, non-informative. Consider a crime scene. Security cameras show the burglar opening the safe on the first attempt, using the twelve-digit code. Detective Alphonse suggests that the burglar guessed the code. This theory is non-informative. A clueless burglar could have guessed anything. Detective Bertrand suggests that the robbery was an inside job. This is informative. Only an informed burglar would have been likely to enter the correct code. This is an important distinction. Non-informative theories are at the mercy of the relevant set of possibilities. We might entertain the probability of guessing a three-digit code. But as we add digits, the set of possible codes grows, and the likelihood of guessing the correct code drops. By contrast, extra digits will not affect the performance of the informed burglar.
On the burden of proof, you talk about God (that is, the
cause of the universe) as an extra contingent object among objects or a Mickey Mouse.
Nothing is unified or explained or dependent on invisible elephants (or insert
whatever extra contingent objects here). If such nonexistent entities happen to
exist it would make difference to the universe, and they too would only exist
in a manner no different from the universe as a whole; that is, they would
exist derivatively, receiving their existence from the paradigm Existent.
Finally, nothing we observe in the universe causes us to think that such
entities exist, whereas as Cicero put it, “Nature herself has imprinted
on the minds of all the idea of God.”
You seem to be almost contradicting yourself, since you say
that scientific atheism ultimately fails because rational argument ends at some
point. Interestingly, you cite the origin of the universe as a question that
will simply have to be decided as an existential choice about the sort of
person you want to be. (Note that the origin of the universe is one thing I
left out in my nine reasons.) This is very close to my position on the origin
of the universe, but I would add also cosmic fine-tuning and intelligibility to
the list.
On falsifiability, you are making a different point now. OK,
there are different religions, but there is also a lot of overlap between the
monotheistic religions, such as on the point that the universe as an object
created by God ought to reflect his power and wisdom. (True, a dominant Muslim
sect would overemphasize God’s will over his intellect, and this would have
different metaphysical implications, such as ruling out secondary causes and
the very possibility of natural laws). But this proves my point, as your very
conception of God has nontrivial metaphysical implications.
You say the Gnostics said the creator God was evil, but it
is my understanding that they believed matter was evil because it was created
by an evil demon, not God. (This is why they believed, for instance, that Jesus
was only a spirit who gave off the superficial appearance of having human
flesh). The demon was using the physical world to blind us from the truth of
the One true God. There is perhaps a lot of overlap here with Greek thought. As
Thomas Torrance put it,
Christian belief in the goodness and integrity of the physical universe…played an incalculable part in transforming the ancient worldview. It destroyed the Platonic and Aristotelian idea that matter is, if not evil, the raw material of corruption and unreality and the source of disorder in the universe, and it also ruled entirely out of consideration the pessimistic views of nature that emanated from the dualist sects such as the Manichaeans and Gnostics, thereby emancipating the material reality of the universe for serious scientific attention.
You say that the unification of physics with astronomy
entails atheism because the celestial realm is now demystified (supposedly God
was a cosmic teapot hidden somewhere in the celestial realm). So heads you win,
tails I lose? Remember when you said that naturalism doesn’t entail complete
reductionism? (The last step of reductionism is the unification of physics with
chemistry, which was expected to follow Einstein’s unification of gravity with
spacetime and Maxwell’s unification of light and optics with electromagnetism).
Two points. First, the level of demystification achieved
came at a cost for the naturalist. It came with the introduction of a
theological concept: universal natural laws.
The orthodox view of the nature of the laws of physics contains a long list of tacitly assumed properties. The laws are regarded…as immutable, eternal, infinitely precise mathematical relationships that transcend the physical universe, and were imprinted on it at the moment of its birth from “outside,” like a maker’s mark, and have remained unchanging ever since…In addition, it is assumed that the physical world is affected by the laws, but the laws are completely impervious to what happens in the universe…It is not hard to discover where this picture of physical laws comes from: it is inherited directly from monotheism, which asserts that a rational being designed the universe according to a set of perfect laws. And the asymmetry between immutable laws and contingent states mirrors the asymmetry between God and nature: the universe depends utterly on God for its existence, whereas God’s existence does not depend on the universe… (Paul Davies and Niels Henrik Gregersen, eds. Information and the Nature of Reality: From Physics to Metaphysics)
This is why the concept of universal natural laws is hotly
debated among philosophers of science. The “scientific view of the world” is
thoroughly theological. This is why Davies would say that all scientists
(whether atheist or theist) essentially presuppose a theological worldview.
Second, the demystification is not as clear-cut as you make
it out to be:
It is not always realised how exceedingly abstract is the information that theoretical physics has to give. It lays down certain fundamental equations which enable it to deal with the logical structure of events, while leaving it completely unknown what is the intrinsic character of the events that have the structure…All that physics gives us is certain equations giving abstract properties of their changes. But as to what it is that changes, and what it changes from and to—as to this, physics is silent. (Bertrand Russell, My Philosophical Development, p. 13)
Yes, unguided natural processes are dependent on deep time
and chance, but the inverse does not hold for God. What are billions of years
to God who is outside time? Also, if we can see that our physical laws are
tuned to permit intelligent life, it seems less a coincidence that I couldn’t
observe a smaller universe. The universe was probably rigged so that it could
produce the building blocks necessary for life. (However, we currently have no
theory for the origin of life, so it is pure speculation to extrapolate from
necessary to sufficient conditions for complex life).
On your last point, you basically asserted that our values
must be arbitrary and subjective and could not be based on anything objective.
I would agree only if I thought there were no God.
*****
Ben Cain’s Fifth Reply and Conclusion:
I agree there’s a difference between arguments for theism, and arguments within theism. Unfortunately, your
argument for theism assumes that theism counts as a good explanation, and you
listed nine facts that theism supposedly explains better than does naturalism.
My main criticism has to do with that assumption and so it does undermine your
argument for theism. If theism never counts as a good explanation for anything,
then obviously your argument for theism—which, again, is that theism explains
nine facts well—doesn’t work, because it can’t even get started. Remember that
you’re the one who appealed to theism’s explanatory power. You’re the one who
assumed that “God did it” counts as a valid explanation. I disagree with that
assumption made by your argument for theism. You think you can accept science
and philosophy along with theism, because you believe theism is well-supported
by reason. But I think the more rational
you attempt to make theism, the more your god becomes an idol, which makes your
theism incoherent because you’ll need to go back and forth between the
intuitive picture of God as a personal designer who’s like us, and the
transcendent, esoterically-rational picture of an entity that’s unlike anything
in the universe.
If God were plainly the cause of the universe so that we
could read the signs embedded in the effects that indicate the nature of their
divine cause, then indeed the universe would testify to God’s existence, as
theists imagine. And indeed, if we were talking about nature as the animists
conceived of it with their anthropomorphic projections, then sure: a personal
source of a living universe would make sense. But this isn’t the universe that
scientists found. It makes more sense to explain life and intelligence as
emergent phenomena than as metaphysically primary, because the vast majority of
the universe is lifeless and mindless. Saying that a person created nature
makes no sense, because our concept of personhood has implications that
wouldn’t apply to a monotheistic God. A person requires not just a brain but a society. When a person grows up in the
wild with no parents, he or she becomes feral and loses the quality of being a
person, because that creature would have no language or culture. If God is
timeless and doesn’t develop or learn, God is no kind of person that we
understand at all. In fact, calling
both God and a human “persons” would require equivocation: the theist would be
illicitly assuming two definitions of “person,” because of the obvious differences
between our and God’s intelligence, intentions, and will.
Computation seems to be insufficient for a broad kind of
intelligence, but we know a lot more about intelligence than just that negative
likelihood. We know, for example, that we have to be taught to fulfill our
potential for intelligence, not just individually but collectively in history.
We know intelligence is based in the cerebral cortex, we know other animal
species have degrees of intelligence, and we know intelligence is an evolutionary
adaptation and that it evolved from stimulus-response behaviours. None of this
would apply to God, so calling God and us intelligent involves an equivocation.
We plan ahead by thinking of alternatives, because we live in a dangerous
environment and need advantages to survive. Our intelligence can impact the
world because our mind is seated in the brain, which is wired into our physical
body, and our body can interact with the rest of the physical world. Again,
none of that would apply to God. God needn’t fear anything, so why would he
need to plan to avoid certain possibilities? Why not just blindly create all
possible universes? And the Western monotheist’s God has no body so we have no
idea how his intelligence could have natural effects.
I agree that all
rational explanations are incomplete, if only because our concepts are
simplifications. That’s why theism isn’t a rational explanation, because
positing God is supposed to explain absolutely everything in the universe.
Incoherence isn’t a result just of an explanation’s incompleteness, although
the attempt to fit together incomplete explanations or models can result in an
incoherent synthesis. Theism is
incoherent for lots of reasons, but the one that’s emerged in our discussion is
that the philosophical theist’s conception of God as an intelligent designer
must take seriously the anthropocentric metaphor of the personal nature of
ultimate reality, and this conception conflicts with the philosophical doubts
about naïve, exoteric religion, which imply the mystic’s conception of God as
transcendent and entirely beyond our comprehension (our metaphors being futile
and ultimately misleading).
I agree, by the way, that the notion of a natural law is
crypto-theistic. This raises the question why atheistic scientists would adhere
to that deistic notion. I’m pretty sure the answer is just that most scientists
are scientistic, meaning that they’re
dismissive of philosophy and so they don’t take the time to consider the
philosophical implications of their discourse.
For me, though, a deeper question is why we should trust our
cognitive powers when it comes to the ultimate questions, especially if we end
up flattering ourselves with theistic answers. I agree with mystics who say
that exoteric theism stems from an ethical
flaw. It’s unimaginative or vain for us to think of ultimate reality as being
anything like us! Even if it turns out that God does exist and did create the
universe, I suspect God would reward atheists more highly than theists, because
anthropocentrism would be a sin, stemming from fear or vanity, whereas
reflective atheists are more likely to be humble. Atheists who appreciate the
existential absurdity of our situation, who believe that whatever strangeness
is at the bottom of nature doesn’t at all favour humans and that the emergence
of life is a tragic accident should have no cosmic reason to boast. By
contrast, theists have more of a reason for being complacent, because they can
claim to be in some proper accord with primary reality. Atheistic naturalism entails that absurdity—not a perfect plan—is
fundamental to our situation, and so we’re permanently homeless, despite
our restlessness in replacing the scary wilderness with an artificial world in
which we’re much more comfortable. We’re
lost in the universe, because our intelligence enables us to see that we’re
alienated from nature, which is why we must struggle to survive and why our
domination has the unintended consequence of corrupting and thus dooming us. Contrary
to your quotation of Thomas Torrance, Pauline, Gnostic Christianity is correct
in its Platonic suspicion that nature is fallen, that our souls don’t belong in
the material world but that we’re trapped here.
Reason is a burden to
bear, since philosophy thrusts this subversive viewpoint on us, which is why I
think philosophical theism misses the mark. The problem with atheism or
naturalism isn’t that the exoteric idea of God should be taken seriously. On
the contrary, we should pay more attention to the mystical, cosmicist suspicion
that fundamental reality is bound to be indifferent towards us—which is
humiliating. Any other kind of cosmology or metaphysics sets up an idol that
flatters or otherwise corrupts us. So say Judaism and elements of Islam. This means that new atheists and secular
humanists can be as wrongheaded as naïve theists, from my perspective.
Neither is nearly humble enough; neither has wrestled with the Nietzschean or
Lovecraftian implications of naturalism.
If I were a theist, I’d press the pragmatic or existentialist
line of argument. For example, Richard Dawkins is fond of saying that just
because a belief is comforting doesn’t mean it’s true, which is correct. But
Dawkins doesn’t go on to consider whether it’s possible or wise to ensure that
all our beliefs are true. From Dawkins’ biological perspective, we’re all
animals with a highly irrational side, so why should we expect that we’re
fundamentally concerned with factual truth? Of course, we’re internally
conflicted since we do have the scientific capacity for objectivity, but that
means we must reconcile the nonrational and rational sides of ourselves.
Dawkins does this only weakly by admiring the alleged beauty and wonder of
nature. Meanwhile, he’s a secularist, and for centuries secular society has
been endeavoring, as I said, to bury nature beneath the artificial cities we
seem to prefer. If all worldviews have
mythical, intuitive, and artistic underpinnings, the difference between theism
and atheistic worldviews must be more aesthetic or ethical than empirical.
The fundamental philosophical issue needn’t be truth. In fact,
truth-as-correspondence may be in the same category as natural law: both
notions may derive from an outmoded theistic worldview.
No comments:
Post a Comment