[The following is drawn from my email exchange with Darwin Skeptic. I took thematically-related sections of my messages and assembled them
into an article. So you can read my stand-alone case against philosophical theism without
having to read the longer email exchange. Enjoy!]
*****
Philosophy, the relatively independent, objective exercise
of reason in response to profound questions can address theism or any
other subject, but it doesn’t support theism well, by making theistic beliefs more rational than atheistic ones.
Atheism is more rational than theism, as far as philosophers are typically
concerned. Not everything that philosophers address is illuminated by their
ruminations, because unlike science, philosophy is partly artistic and
literary, which means it includes speculations and rhetorical rationalizations
of cultural prejudices. At its best, though, philosophers provide arguments or
illustrations that revolutionize culture or that at least separate the enlightened
intellectuals from the hoi polloi. Analytic philosophers currently focus on
science and rigorous analysis, minimizing speculation and rhetoric and thus the
artistic side of philosophy, at the cost of making their tedious, hyper-detailed
writings culturally irrelevant since they’ve had to overlook the bigger issues.
Atheism and the Danger of Freedom of Thought
In any case, even before offering an atheistic argument or
looking at any theistic proof that a religious philosopher might provide, we
shouldn’t expect philosophy to establish that a personal creator of the
universe exists. After all, Western philosophy grew out of a rejection of
popular religion. From Thales to Aristotle, the ancient Greek philosophers
ridiculed the popular notions of gods. The Presocratics overthrew the Olympian
pantheon, crediting various material or impersonal powers with being the
foundations of all other things. They thus made nonsense of the self-serving
metaphors we naively proffer to humanize that which would plainly have to be
unlike anything in nature, to be the precondition of all knowable categories
and particulars, including persons. Plato’s Parable of the Cave famously
substitutes goodness for God. Aristotle’s divine being, the primary cause or
unmoved mover, retained the personal quality of being able to think, but only
because the essence of this being is to reflect on itself. Aristotle’s theology
is thus deistic rather than theistic: his God doesn’t create nature but only
inspires it as its final cause or purpose, as opposed to being nature’s
efficient, mechanical cause. Aristotle’s deity can’t think about or perceive
anything other than itself, because doing so would render it imperfect and thus
it would cease to exist as the eternal, perfect being which all lower beings
look up to.
Such is an example of a philosopher’s god. Of course,
Aristotle was only meditating on the celestial motions of what we now know are
planets, not perfect persons in any way. But the point is that philosophical
reflection on the question of theism in the West has historically acted as a corrective
to the intuitive, emotional, faith-based conceptions of divinity. Vulgar
religion isn’t argumentative; instead, it’s tribal, the gods being mental
projections that celebrate the character of the believers’ culture. To
paraphrase the ancient Greek philosopher Xenophanes, if horses or lions could
believe in gods, their gods would look like horses or lions. Likewise,
aggressive cultures worship angry, jealous gods that threaten to annihilate
their worshippers if they don’t conquer some earthly region or other. And as
Nietzsche pointed out, victimized people such as the early Christians worship a
forgiving deity that prefers weakness to strength, poverty to wealth, modesty
to pride. Christianity thus begins with slave morality, because popular,
exoteric theism in general is a pre-reflective cultural expression quite
inseparable from its religious practices. Indeed, it’s philosophy that
distinguishes theistic beliefs from the religion so that the religious ideas
can be scrutinized without any social commitment to the religion.
In the West, then, philosophy has historically challenged
conventional wisdom in so far as the latter was propped up by prejudices and
mass confusions. For that reason Socrates was executed, and so he became
the secular Christ figure, the martyr for the elite exercise of reason on
behalf of truths which the mob is unwilling to accept, including the truths of
naturalism and atheism. Ancient Greco-Roman philosophy was reborn in Europe
during the Renaissance, after what historians call the Middle Ages. Why the
division rather than historical continuity? Because what passed for philosophy
during the Middle Ages was dogmatic and in the hands of the Roman Catholic
Church which was opposed to philosophy as such; indeed, the Church effectively
demonized philosophy and science as witchcraft and the like, because
free-thinking tended to depart from Church teachings. The essence of philosophy
was thus a crime punishable by death. For example, the Aristotelian proposition
that God can’t think about anything other than himself was banned by the Church
in 1270, and between 1210 and 1277 the Church banned many other philosophical
statements. But these bans proved ineffective, and despite Aquinas’s grand
synthesis of Christianity and Aristotelianism, which was meant to tame the
latter for the glory of the former, the act of reading the ancient texts gave
some Scholastics an inkling of genuine philosophy. They turned into skeptics
who denied that reason could support faith, since they believed reason couldn’t
even prove that the external world exists. These skeptics countered the
rationalists who adhered to the Church’s bans by confining themselves to
pondering how God could act contrary to the condemned parts of Aristotle’s
philosophy. All of the Scholastics’ arguments, though, were necessarily limited
and often whispered rather than written, since they had to be acceptable to the
Church for both the books and the authors to avoid being burned. For example,
Nicholas of Autrecourt had to recant his skepticism and burn all his writings
in 1347.
When more of the ancient texts became available towards the
end of the Medieval Period, they sparked a full-blown humanistic revolution in
Europe that set off the Age of Reason, which included the rise of modern
science and the Enlightenment, the latter being the enforcing of secular
philosophy to establish a culture of liberal humanism. Enlightenment
philosophers were authentically philosophical because they were free to pursue
ideas wherever they led. By contrast, the classic theistic proofs by
Aquinas and the Scholastic philosophers were stale and strained, because their
approach to reason in general was artificially narrow-minded. (Aquinas even admitted
as much on his death bed, calling his life’s work so much “straw.”) Unlike
Socrates, the Church’s intellectuals didn’t love knowledge more than their
skins; those that did were the pagans and heretics from Hypatia to Bruno who
were tortured and murdered by the orthodox Christians. In between the Ages of
Faith and Reason there was a grey area populated by such figures as Descartes,
Leibniz, Spinoza, Locke, and even Newton and Kant. Being men of their time when
the church was still politically powerful, these philosophers and scientists
were partly dogmatists, but they were also partly free thinkers. Most early
modern intellectuals thus argued for both esoteric theism (that is, for a
version of theism or deism which doesn’t sit well with popular religion, the
closer you examine it, seeing through the philosopher’s obfuscations and noble
lies) and liberal secular humanism, because philosophy was still once
again finding its footing. That development culminated in the rabid naturalism
of Nietzsche who predicted the downfall of philosophy itself in our period of
hypermodern malaise.
So the history of Western philosophy should make us
skeptical of philosophical theism. The use of reason in defense of the popular
conception of gods, as being flawless persons who create and miraculously
intervene in nature, tends to be disingenuous. Why? Because there’s
no reason to expect that logic should align with intuition and emotion, and the
popular, theistic (as opposed to deistic, pantheistic, or mystical) conceptions
of gods plainly flow from the latter. When intellectuals begin thinking
freely (and thus philosophically) about theological matters, they inevitably
discover all sorts of gross errors, incoherencies, and other absurdities in the
conventional beliefs. The mob of believers isn’t interested in whether their
religion is rationally justifiable: they want to believe in their gods
because doing so makes them feel better about life and death, and unites their
community in a way that affords its members the chance to be happy. Therefore,
the mob doesn’t include philosophers, because authentic intellectuals (as
opposed to dogmatists and demagogues) stand apart from the crowd, as their
liberated thoughts inevitably have more or fewer subversive implications which
render these intellectuals unpopular.
As partly artistic and rhetorical as it is, compared to
science itself, and thus as capable as it is of arguing for anything under the
sun, philosophy is still ill-suited to establishing the rational superiority of
theism to atheism. The point here is akin to the aphorism about the danger of
trusting in the God of the Gaps. Some theists defend their religion by locating
the work of their deity within a gap in that which is understood with the
ever-expanding body of scientific knowledge, the danger being that science has
tended to fill its gaps, which then falsifies the god that was supposed to be
found there. The gods were once identified with the planets and indeed with all
sorts of forces or powers which were eventually naturalized. Modern
naturalism has thus pushed the gods not just out of our solar system but out of
the whole known universe. Darwin even showed how species could naturally
evolve without any intelligent designer. All that’s left for the theist,
philosophically speaking, is some unknowable, transcendent, supernatural First
Cause which is removed from nature, which isn’t personal, and which
therefore isn’t the theist’s God at all. In line with mysticism, reason
doesn’t establish this source of nature so much as faith does, since this
Source is stipulated to be beyond our understanding.
In any case, the rational, science-centered, and indeed
subversive aspect of philosophy ensures the shakiness of philosophical theism.
This may seem to beg the question against theism, but the judgment here is
based on the historical induction which I’ve outlined above. The theist’s
synthesis of philosophy and religion is dubious at the outset, because the
theist has the audacity to attempt to turn her opponent’s weapon, being
philosophy, against the opponent. This is like saying that guns are best used
in support not of war but of peace. On the contrary, guns can’t help but break
the peace, because to use them is to commit acts of violence. Likewise,
philosophy can’t help but undermine socially useful beliefs and practices, such
as theism and religion, since to think philosophically is precisely to exercise
doubt, to ask deep questions, to demolish everything that’s taken for granted
and to rebuild only what passes the test of rigorous skepticism. Scientists
test their hypotheses with physical experiments, while philosophers test their
speculations and analyses by submitting them to the crucible of limitless
debate. The historical trend of Western philosophers’ skepticism and
subversion isn’t accidental. Western philosophy is defined by the ancient
Greek tradition, and the love of wisdom precludes an equal love of anything
else such as fame, happiness, or power. This means that philosophy is an
obsession with the truth, a dangerous love that disregards its personal and
social consequences. At best, the philosopher trusts that the rational search
for the ultimate truth will benefit the seeker rather than, say, derange her.
It was left for Sade and Nietzsche to point out that the death of God may prove
socially disastrous.
So is theism likely to be rational? To count as a
worthwhile explanation, it would have to increase our understanding to say that
a person created the universe. But the moment of Creation would have been
miraculous and thus inexplicable to us, and the notion of an entirely
immaterial mind runs counter to mountains of evidence. People as we understand
them have minds which depend on physical brains. Where, then, is God’s brain
supposed to be? If God has none, he’s not literally a person, in which case we
must shift from theism to some more esoteric conception, and we’re no longer
talking about philosophical theism. If God has personal qualities, they
should be just as in need of explanation as the qualities of natural persons
which the positing of God is supposed to explain. Again, if God’s qualities are
special in that instead of possessing them, for example, God is identical with
them, in which case God wouldn’t have love but would be love, God
wouldn’t be like any person on Earth. In that case, calling God “personal”
would be vacuous, since God’s thoughts and feelings would have nothing
to do with our kinds of mental states. A useful metaphor for X has to
shed light by including more similarities to than differences from X.
But the more similar God is to a human person, the less explanatory value
theism has, since in that case positing God commits the fallacy of special
pleading. We can’t explain how people came to be in general by saying they
all come from a special person that has roughly the same characteristics as
humans but that for some reason doesn’t himself require any explanation. Such a
pseudo-explanation may comfort the mob, but it doesn’t increase a philosopher’s
understanding. For reasons like these, theism fails as a rational
explanation. But since the stories that are central to theistic religions are poetic
myths, the notion that theism should be held to rational standards in the
first place is wrongheaded.
Theism’s Origin in Animistic and Emotional Projections
To the extent that theism seems to make sense of
otherwise perplexing facts, such as the cosmic fine-tuning of the universe to
support life, our species’ high intelligence, and the consensus about morality,
that’s only because theism is unfalsifiable and could be made compatible
with any conceivable piece of evidence. So theism is a pseudo-explanation
and the rational superiority of theism is an illusion.
Theism is the belief that a perfect person created and
intervenes in the world. Theism itself is thus exoteric, meaning it’s an
expression of our tendency to anthropomorphize whatever we attempt to
understand at the intuitive level. That doesn’t mean theism is thereby false,
since that would be the genetic fallacy. But it does mean that the theistic
notion of ultimate reality or of the source of everything in nature is dubious.
As a refinement of animism, theism is the result of a gradual
disenchantment of the world, as populations fled the wilderness and the life of
hunting and gathering and crowded into walled-off civilizations. This momentous
anthropological shift pushed spirits further and further away until the talk of
gods became vacuous and the gods themselves were vestiges, because we’d
forgotten what they really were. Spirits, angels, demons, faeries, goblins,
ghosts and gods are mental projections. They were the result of naive
attempts to ward off fear of the unknown, by humanizing everything in
experience.
Precisely because people once lacked godlike physical power
in nature, and were only several animal species in the same kingdom as all the
other animals, as opposed to reigning over the planet like we seem to do now,
our distant ancestors could only imagine that nature was tamed. And so
they envisioned that the world is an enormous society: the wind and the rain,
the day and the night could be negotiated with through prayer and rituals,
because everything was alive and mentally active. That way, the powerful human
talent for interpreting the contents of other human minds could be extended to
apply to whatever the ancestors encountered. Animists thus related to the world
much as all children instinctively do, since they regarded everything as imbued
with magical powers and mystery. They could hardly have done otherwise, since
those distant ancestors had no other advantage than their mental power, because
their technology was still primitive. Other animal species had greater speed or
strength, but we excelled in our ability to conceive of mental maps and to make
those maps especially relevant by grounding them in our experience. Thus, our
ancestors could mentally simulate possibilities and judge their worth by
applying familiar criteria such as the rules for social engagement.
In short, the animists didn’t sharply distinguish between
subjects and objects, and so they assumed that spirits were everywhere. That
made sense to the egalitarian, hunter-gatherer societies. Monotheists and
polytheists took those omnipresent spirits and packed them into fewer but
denser forms, as it were. They did so in response to two developments: the vast
increase in human power over nature, thanks at first to farming, and the rise
of great chieftains and kings, and of the more hierarchical nature of civilized
society. The more technological control we had, the less we needed to rely on
compromises with fickle spirits of the wild. And the remaining spirits had to
reflect the new kind of society to fulfill their function of comforting the
masses and providing for the meaning of their life. Thus, the spirits became
gods modeled on monarchical or aristocratic human rulers.
Again, this isn’t to commit the genetic fallacy, by saying
that because theism has a dubious origin, therefore theism is false. My point
in referring to animism isn’t just genealogical, since the current naïve
conception of God as human-like is also more easily understood as being similar
to the ancient animist’s mental projection. So I’m saying the textbook notion
of God as a personal creator of the universe is more simply explained as
resting on anthropomorphic projections than on a real deity. I’m not saying
theism is false or dubious because of its origin; rather, I’m saying theism
more likely has one sort of origin (the deflationary one) than another (the
naïve, literal theistic one).
Theism’s resulting Unfalsifiability and Incoherence
Thus, mysteries such as the natural order, freewill, and the
universality of moral judgments are never explained by appealing directly to
God; instead, their mysteriousness can be neutralized by turning to the
theistic mental projections, to the humanizing filter we lay on top of
what philosophers think of more neutrally as the ultimate ground of Being.
For example, suppose a theist says that the fine-tuning of the universe to
allow for the emergence of intelligent life is expected if we assume theism. This
would assume, in turn, that we would have the foggiest notion of what an
infinite, eternal, supernatural person would want. It assumes the validity
of some divine revelation so that we could (vainly) affirm that God created the
universe primarily because God wanted to create us. But not every
creation myth is so self-serving and myopic. There have been hundreds of
creation myths, some of which treat humanity as a blip in cosmic history.
Hindus say the universe is sustained by Vishnu’s dream, and when he awakens one
of infinitely many cosmic cycles will end. Indeed, why wouldn’t God
create many different universes, including lifeless ones, if he lives forever?
Why wouldn’t God have already created all the universes of the
physicist’s multiverse? What else was God doing before the Big Bang? And so why
wouldn’t God’s plan be unfathomable to us? Clearly, the assumption that God
created this universe because he wanted intelligent life to evolve derives from
the same anthropocentrism that led the animists to socialize nature and the
early theists to pack spirits into king-like rulers whose existence would
thereby validate human civilizations.
So suppose a philosophical theist offers the following sort
of argument:
(1) The universe is mysterious for its tendency to support
intelligent life.
(2) God would want to create such life, whereas atheists
have to leave that cosmic tendency unexplained.
(3) The cosmic tendency makes more sense if God created the
universe than if there were no God.
(4) Therefore, philosophy supports theism better than
atheism.
Similar arguments could be offered featuring other facts or
alleged facts which theism might be expected to explain better than could
naturalistic atheism, including consciousness, freewill, or morality. But (2)
is dubious. Suppose there is a God but he didn’t create our universe; instead,
our universe popped into being, as in quantum mechanics, and life evolved
painstakingly and obviously by accident over billions of years. In that case, a
theist might say that this lack of fine-tuning is likewise evidence of
God’s handiwork, since God would want to hide his role in creating the universe
so that any life forms that happened to evolve wouldn’t depend on God but would
have to fend for themselves and become strong and independent creatures. The
possibilities of what a deity would want are endless—not necessarily for
the deity, but for us, because we perceive through a glass darkly, to borrow
Saint Paul’s expression; we are in full control over how we imagine our gods to
be, what scripture to write or how to interpret it, and what religion to belong
to.
In speaking of divinity in the theistic manner, we are
speaking only about ourselves, about our anthropomorphic projections, our
societal structures and cultural preferences. Again, this has been
understood in the West since Xenophanes. The comparative mythologist Joseph
Campbell popularized this point with his distinction between the futile
metaphors we use to understand ultimate reality, and the mystical experience of
God as the oneness of being. To say that God would want to create life, because
this or that myth or creed says so is to get caught up with the anthropocentric
screen. The source of theism’s unfalsifiability is that we control
the metaphors and the interpretations, and thus we can ensure that our religion
or theistic model conforms to every conceivable state of affairs. Theism in
its exoteric aspect, which includes the metaphor of ultimate being’s
personhood, is a fiction in that the popular theistic ideas are mental
projections. And so theists can dictate their picture of God just as any human
author can decide what to include in her fictional story. Christianity is a
marvelous example of this subjectivity, since despite the utterly anti-American
implications of the New Testament, the intrinsic amorphousness of all theistic
deities permits Americans to interpret Jesus as blessing their every imperial
adventure, capitalistic idolatry, and racist and sexist bigotry, just as the
early Catholics had done in defense of their accidental, anti-Jesus empire.
There is no need, however, to concede premise (1), since
there’s no need merely to imagine a world in which life evolved
painstakingly and accidentally over billions of years. That is in fact how life
evolved in this universe, which means the universe is wildly hostile to life.
It’s true that if the initial parameters of the Big Bang had been only slightly
different, life as we know it wouldn’t have been possible. This doesn’t mean
that no unknown form of life could eventually have evolved in those vastly
different universes. After all, the development of those universes would
have corresponded to altogether different models and so we could only barely
guess at their endpoints. We don’t even know for certain the endpoint of our
universe, because of the surprises of dark matter and energy, so we certainly
aren’t entitled to say that even though it seems to have taken billions of
years for life accidentally to emerge here, no strange kind of life could ever
emerge in any other kind of universe.
Indeed, it made some sense to speak of the source of nature
as having us in mind, when we assumed the universe was no larger than our solar
system and the Earth was at its center, as it seemed from the ancients’ limited
vantage point. Now that we know the universe is vaster than we can fathom and
is hardly full of life, and that phenotypes did evolve partly due to the random
transmission of genes from one generation to the next, as selected by the
different environments—not to mention the many other accidents such as the
meteor impact which made Earth safe for mammals—it seems farfetched to maintain
that the cause of any apparent cosmic fine-tuning was likely the human-friendly
intentions of a deity. We don’t know that the emergence of life is bizarre,
because we don’t know that other kinds of life couldn’t evolve under very
different conditions. Moreover, this sort of theistic argument would
establish at best a God of the Gaps, since the fine-tuning is only currently
mysterious. Were naturalists to explain the fine-tuning, such as by further
justifying the multiverse theory, this reason for theism would disappear. And
as I said earlier, scientists have tended to fill their gaps.
Another problem is with (3), which is that theism isn’t a good explanation of anything.
For example, theists are guilty of special pleading on behalf of their deity. There’s
no increase of understanding in saying that intelligent life was allowed to
emerge, because the universe was created by an
intelligent life form. Theism doesn’t thereby explain the existence of
intelligent life at all, but only presupposes the existence of
intelligence, using our interpretation of it, as I said, as a magic top hat to
hide a rabbit or anything else we’d need to feel better about some situation in
which we find ourselves. If God were plainly the cause of the universe so that
we could read the signs embedded in the effects that indicate the nature of
their divine cause, then indeed the universe would testify to God’s existence,
as theists imagine. And indeed, if we were talking about nature as the animists
conceived of it with their anthropomorphic projections, then sure: a personal
source of a living universe would make sense. But this isn’t the universe that
scientists found. It makes more sense to explain life and intelligence as
emergent phenomena than as metaphysically primary, because the vast majority of
the universe is lifeless and mindless.
Saying that a person created nature makes no sense, because
our concept of personhood has implications that wouldn’t apply to a monotheist’s
God. A person requires not just a brain but a society. When a person grows up in the wild with no parents, he or
she becomes feral and loses the quality of being a person, because that
creature would have no language or culture. If God is timeless and doesn’t
develop or learn, God is no kind of person that we understand at all. In fact, calling both God and a
human “persons” would require equivocation: the theist would be illicitly
assuming two definitions of “person,” because of the obvious differences
between our and God’s intelligence, intentions, and will. Theism is incoherent for lots of reasons, one of which is that the
philosophical theist’s conception of God as an intelligent designer must take
seriously the anthropocentric metaphor of the personal nature of ultimate
reality, and this conception conflicts with the philosophical doubts about
naïve, exoteric religion, which imply the mystic’s conception of God as
transcendent and entirely beyond our comprehension (our metaphors being futile
and ultimately misleading). That is, the more rational a theist attempts to
make her belief in God, the more that god becomes an idol, which makes her
theism incoherent because she’ll need to go back and forth between the
intuitive picture of God as a personal designer who’s like us, and the
transcendent, esoterically-rational picture of an entity that’s unlike anything
in the universe.
Rational Standards for Theistic Explanations
Theism doesn’t have to be scientific to be true. However, to
be philosophical and not just dogmatic, theism must be rational as
opposed to purely faith-based. Therefore, philosophical theism must adhere to
the principles of critical thinking as these apply to arguments and
explanations. This applies, then, to any argument for philosophical theism claiming
that theism makes sense of various phenomena, whereas the naturalist is
supposed to struggle with them. According to this sort of argument, theism
tells us the cause (God’s intelligent design) of certain facts (cosmic
fine-tuning, existence of consciousness and morality, and so on). The point
would be that theism increases the probability of these facts, whereas atheism
makes them unlikely. Specifically, theism would make for a valid inference
to the best explanation of those facts. Therefore, this argument for theism
must include a valid case of abductive reasoning—not according to strict
scientific standards, but according to general rational ones.
One such standard is that an explanation must add to our
understanding, instead of piling one mystery on top of another; that is, a
rational explanation mustn’t be itself mystifying. Moreover, the explanation
must be a form of reasoning in the first place, not purely a work of fictional
art. That is, we must be dealing with intelligible propositions whose contents
aren’t entirely poetic, subjective, or vacuous. Also, a rational explanation
mustn’t be circular, meaning it must explain Y in terms of X, where X and Y
aren’t the same in relevant respects. So for philosophical theism to provide
the cause of cosmic fine-tuning and all the rest, it must first be a valid form
of causal reasoning. I’ve argued that it’s not and I’ve even explained why it’s
not and why we shouldn’t expect that it would be, because of how religion
evolved from anthropocentric mental projections in the animistic phase of
hunter-gatherers, and how its propositions function as poetic myths. Theism
doesn’t rationally explain anything; therefore, it doesn’t explain various
facts or alleged facts a theist might raise.
Positing God as a cause doesn’t increase our
understanding, because God would be the biggest mystery and miracle of them
all. If a theist wishes to counter this point by leaning on the
anthropomorphic metaphors, according to which God is rather like a human person,
she’ll only push the mystification back a step. This is because the literal
conception of a personal deity quickly becomes incoherent and thus, once again,
empty of explanatory content. For example, God’s mind would have no brain and
his thoughts and feelings would have to be sequential and temporally bound,
whereas God is supposed to be eternal; moreover, God would have to be perfect,
whereas there’s no such thing as a perfect human person, by definition, since
the meaning of person’s life is to struggle to overcome obstacles such as those
that arise from her internally divided nature (the older and newer evolutionary
layers of her brain). In other words, by our lights, a person is essentially
flawed and mortal, and so the notion of an immortal, perfect person makes no
sense. Notice, for example, how the New Testament’s portrayal of Jesus’
alleged perfection works by skipping over his adolescence so the reader doesn’t
have to wonder how Jesus overcame the awkward years of puberty and acting-out,
and how those formative years would have shaped his adulthood—as happens in the
case of every genuine person as opposed to a cardboard-cutout, fictional
character.
Theistic language is properly poetic and subjective,
which allows Christians, for example, to interpret their scripture in all sorts
of contrary ways. Is a scriptural passage meant to be taken literally or is
it metaphorical? Is it meant to be prophetic and to speak to everyone, even
millennia after it was written? Is it inerrant or did God only inspire the
human authors so that parts of the Bible are fallible, reflecting their
historical context? There are no objective criteria for settling such disputes
for theists, so they end up appealing to a Holy Spirit which supposedly guides
their interpretations, but this is a fancy way of admitting that biblical truth
is entirely subjective. In any case, poetic, subjective statements are
devoid of explanatory power, which is what I meant by calling theism
unfalsifiable. The point isn’t that theism is unscientific, but that
it’s rationally empty as a kind of talk about causal relations. The theist can
interpret God as the cause of anything, because God’s mind acts as a magic top
hat out of which the theist can pull a rabbit or a dove or whatever else she
happens to want. For example, the theist can say God intervenes in our life
sometimes but not all the time, and since God works in mysterious ways and it’s
sinful to put God to the test, there’s no way to predict when or how God will
act. Sometimes, according to conventional theistic wisdom, God answers our
prayers by saying “No,” but it would be futile for us to attempt to understand
why God acts or doesn’t act. That’s the whole point of the Book of Job.
By welding together the wildly-incompatible Old and New
Testaments, Christians ensured that their theism, in particular, would be
untestable, which is why their religion has been able to last for centuries.
The more foolhardy prophets who stood by their clear-cut declarations were
swiftly refuted by facts, and so their cults fell by the wayside. Only a
creed with primarily subjective content can be flexible enough to appeal to
anyone at any time, and thus only such a creed can serve a long-lasting global
religion. Similarly, so-called psychics like John Edward can claim to read
anyone’s mind on TV, by playing a sophisticated game of twenty questions with
the audience member (as explained hilariously in a South Park episode). The
audience member does all the work, so the psychic merely has to speak vaguely enough
at first, narrowing his statements as the member inadvertently reveals more and
more by her answers. It’s also how fortune cookies function: the reader does
all the work of applying the text to her life, because the text is treated as
poetry rather than as an objective statement of testable fact. Subjective truth
and emotional appeal have their advantages, of course; alas, one such advantage
isn’t that a work of art that functions in those ways can serve as a rational
explanation.
Finally, theism is obviously circular as an explanation
of anything to do with reason, meaning, design, or value, since God, the
purported cause of these phenomena, would himself have such properties, so it
would be like explaining the existence of trees by saying they all come from a
big tree. It’s actually a case of equivocation, since only most members of
a kind would thereby be explained by appealing to a special member of the same
kind. If we proceed to deny that that special member itself requires an
explanation, we’ve likely committed the fallacy of special pleading, as I’ve said above. The theist can say God doesn’t have his properties
but somehow equals them, but that doesn’t work, as I’ve explained: again, it
makes the concept of God bewildering, and it equivocates on God’s personhood
since God would thus be quite unlike any human person.
Why Theists should be Pragmatists or Existentialists
The problem I’ve
raised is that once you attempt to philosophize your way to theism, you begin
to ask subversive questions about the vulgar conceptions of God, which leads
you to a mystical idea of God’s transcendence, and that idea is virtually
equivalent to atheism, since it defines away God’s personhood as a naïve or
vain anthropocentric projection. The mystical “theist” can no longer appeal
to that transcendent God by way of offering a rational explanation for anything,
because that God is unknowable and no such explanation would add to our
understanding. But if the philosopher persists in rationalizing her preference
for a personal God, she can turn her religion into a pseudoscience, as in the
case of Christian Creationism which treats Genesis as though it were a science
textbook. Philosophy should push us
towards atheism, and philosophical
theism can’t help but objectify God, because reason is our main tool for
controlling things by understanding them, by carving them up into conceptual
boxes and analyzing the information for advantages and weaknesses.
What philosophical theism gains in a plausible concession that
God would have to be beyond our paltry metaphors—meaning that the metaphors
would misrepresent rather than provide partial truth (the partial truth would
be an idol, which is the main point of Judaism and perhaps Islam, which
Christianity contradicts)—it loses in the implication that philosophical theism becomes equivalent to
atheism: God, mystically
defined, becomes impersonal, an absolute emptiness (as in
Buddhism) which is beyond all objects and limited conceptions, and thus beyond
the comparison with any sort of mere person. Such a deity can’t be used in any
rational explanation, because it’s useless to explain something more
understandable in terms of something far less so.
The failure of philosophical theism leaves me with the
question of why we should trust our cognitive powers when it comes to the
ultimate questions, especially if we end up flattering ourselves with theistic
answers. I agree with mystics who say that exoteric theism stems from an ethical flaw. It’s unimaginative or vain
for us to think of ultimate reality as being anything like us! Even if it turns
out that God does exist and did create the universe, I suspect God would reward
atheists more highly than theists, because anthropocentrism would be a sin, stemming
from fear or vanity, whereas reflective atheists are more likely to be humble.
Atheists who appreciate the existential absurdity of our situation, who believe
that whatever strangeness is at the bottom of nature doesn’t at all favour
humans and that the emergence of life is a tragic accident should have no
cosmic reason to boast. By contrast, theists have more of a reason for being
complacent, because they can claim to be in accord with primary
reality. Atheistic naturalism entails
that absurdity—not a perfect plan—is fundamental to our situation, and so
we’re permanently homeless, despite our restlessness in replacing the scary
wilderness with an artificial world in which we’re much more comfortable. We’re lost in the universe, because our
intelligence enables us to see that we’re alienated from nature, which is why
we must struggle to survive and why our domination has the unintended
consequence of corrupting and thus dooming us.
Reason is a burden to bear, since philosophy thrusts this
subversive viewpoint on us, which is why I think philosophical theism misses
the mark. The problem with atheism or naturalism isn’t that the exoteric idea
of God should be taken seriously. On the contrary, we should pay more attention
to the mystical, cosmicist suspicion that fundamental reality is bound to be
indifferent towards us—which is humiliating. Any other kind of cosmology or
metaphysics sets up an idol that flatters or otherwise corrupts us. So say
Judaism and elements of Islam. This means
that new atheists and secular humanists can be as wrongheaded as naïve theists,
from my perspective. Neither is nearly humble enough; neither has wrestled
with the Nietzschean or Lovecraftian implications of naturalism.
If I were a theist, I’d press the pragmatic or
existentialist line of argument. For example, Richard Dawkins is fond of saying
that just because a belief is comforting doesn’t mean it’s true, which is
correct. But Dawkins doesn’t go on to consider whether it’s possible or wise to
ensure that all our beliefs are true. From Dawkins’ biological perspective,
we’re all animals with a highly irrational side, so why should we expect that
we’re fundamentally concerned with factual truth? Of course, we’re internally
conflicted since we do have the scientific capacity for objectivity, but that
means we must reconcile the nonrational and rational sides of ourselves.
Dawkins does this only weakly by admiring the alleged beauty and wonder of
nature. Meanwhile, he’s a secularist, and for centuries secular society has
been endeavoring, as I said, to bury nature beneath the artificial cities we
seem to prefer. If all worldviews have
mythical, intuitive, and artistic underpinnings, the difference between theism
and atheistic worldviews must be more aesthetic or ethical than empirical.
The fundamental philosophical issue needn’t be truth. In fact,
truth-as-correspondence may be in the same category as natural law: both
notions may derive from an outmoded theistic worldview.
No comments:
Post a Comment