In Morality and Aesthetics, I argue that an aesthetic
conception of what we ought to do should replace the moral view, since morality
is as defunct as exoteric theism. The aesthetic conception includes the
distinctions between ugliness and beauty, and between cliché and originality.
The former distinction identifies ugliness as a startling reminder of our
existential situation, including our mortality which horrifies us. The latter
one amounts to the difference between conformity and rebellion, prescribing
that we should resist degrading natural processes and social traditions instead
of succumbing to them with no creative vision. From a broader aesthetic
standpoint, each side of an issue should be appraised according to artistic
standards, and then a judgment should be made as to which side is aesthetically
preferable, just as though the appraiser were evaluating two paintings
side-by-side in a gallery. To clarify further how the aesthetic norms would
work outside of aesthetics proper (painting, sculpture, music, etc), I’d like
to apply what I said to two hot-button issues: abortion and gay marriage.
The Mediocre Art of the Pro-life and Pro-choice Positions
According to what I’ll call the Rule of Infotainment’s
Antithetical Relation to Philosophy, the more a philosophical issue appears in
the news, the more the discussion of that issue is characterized by confusion.
There are at least two reasons for this. First, when an issue is discussed not
just once but repeatedly in the mainstream media, especially on the American
24-hour cable news stations (Fox, MSNBC, CNN), this indicates a high public
interest in the issue, but since the majority are opposed to, or ignorant of,
philosophical standards of argument, those people will degrade the discussion
with their biases and fallacies. To please their audience, the news stations
will dutifully reflect the public’s cognitive deficiencies, because of the
second reason which is the following. As is well-known, the corporate media are
currently in the business mainly of entertaining rather than investigating or
educating, and so the media are more interested in pleasing the intellectually
lazy members of the public than in challenging them with rigorous analyses.
Both abortion and gay marriage are highly controversial and thus popular
subjects of conversation, especially in socially conservative places like the
US, which means that, as these issues are sliced and diced on the major cable
news shows, the quality of the public discussion of them is bound to be
appalling. This is certainly the case regarding abortion.
The moral issue of abortion is whether parents should be
able to terminate their fetus or whether the fetus has the right to live, in
which case abortion amounts to murder. Now, the expression “pro-life” is an
abuse of language, one which is more clumsy than bold since the abuse is
unintentional. Obviously, the issue isn’t as general as the question of life or
death, since most of the anti-abortion folks are in favour of killing nonhuman
animals for food and don’t contend that all animals have a moral right to live.
Even the slogan “pro human life” would be a misnomer, since the anti-abortion
side tends to favour war and capital punishment. The slogan “pro innocent human
life” would be counterproductive, since it would call attention to the fact
that whatever you think of a fetus, it’s far too early to speak of whether a
person has lived well or badly, before the person has done anything. A fetus isn’t
innocent as much as morally neutral, since the fetus could develop into a saint
or into an evil-doer.
The reason that one side nevertheless favours the slogan
“pro-life” appears to be that this slogan (very superficially) handles the
primary retort which is stunningly hardly ever heard in the mainstream media.
This retort is that a fetus isn’t a person, that is, a member of the species Homo
sapiens--especially if we’re talking about the first trimester when the
vast majority of abortions are performed in the US. The anti-abortion
crowd attempts to get around this fact by pretending that the issue is only
whether a fetus is alive in general--which it may well be in a biological
sense, if something as simple as a virus is considered thusly alive. Pro-lifers
then equivocate, shifting from talk of life to talk of human life, leaping to
the conclusion that because a fetus is biologically alive (like a virus), the
fetus has the right to live (like a human person). Because this fallacy is here
so recklessly committed, it calls to mind our irrational nature and our slavery
to instinct, to genetic manipulation, and to social pressures, which in turn
remind us of our existential predicament.
Thus, the so-called pro-life side is hideous to look upon.
Their hyperbolic outcries at rallies, as well as the evasive talking-points of
their professional defenders are like so many grating noises from a fingernail
running down a chalkboard. Their placards depicting bloody infants are
shamefully irrelevant, and because those placards are created out of ignorance
of the point at which most abortions occur, what’s shameful is the pro-lifers’
lack of humility, given that we’re all bound to so err at times because of our
animal nature. That is to say, the anti-abortion side is guilty of the cliché
of being overwhelmed by natural and social forces instead of artistically using
or rebelling against them, even if only with a trace of humility or shame.
However, the anti-abortion side makes a comeback with its
theistic response that even a first trimester fetus is a human person, with the
right to live, because this fetus is supernaturally linked to an immaterial
spirit. At first glance, the theistic invention of the immortal spirit is a
creative response to the fact of natural death. However, there’s a difference
between art and delusion. Art should benefit the user by uplifting her,
enabling her to overcome obstacles by opening up an elevated perspective.
Delusions, or fantasies that invite a retreat rather than a transformation of natural
reality, are traps that stultify rather than dignify the victim. Whether theism
is aesthetically praiseworthy or delusory is a big question I won’t try to
answer here. Theism’s certainly irrational, but that doesn’t settle the matter.
(See Theism. And secular humanism is irrational too.) At any
rate, the artistic merit of inventing the spirit (or of interpreting
consciousness as being spiritual in the theistic sense) and then of assigning
this essence of personhood to a speck of cells is questionable. The many
fallacies sustaining theistic notions do count against theism’s artistic value,
for the above reason regarding cliché. But theistic religion has clearly been
crucial to social cohesion for thousands of years. It’s possible that theism
once had artistic merit but that presently theism functions as a delusion, in
which case the theistic notion of personhood wouldn’t save the pro-life
position, after all, aesthetically speaking.
What of the so-called pro-choice side? “Pro-choice” is an
interesting label since it calls attention to a weakness of the argument in
favour of the choice to abort. The pro-choice side says that since a first
trimester fetus isn’t a person but merely part of the woman’s body, the woman,
together with her partner, have the right to choose what to do with that body
part. The opponent sometimes replies that even if no fetus is actually a
full-grown person, every fetus is potentially one. The pro-choicer then
sometimes attempts to parody this reply by saying that sperm released from
masturbation is potentially a person and so the pro-life crowd should be just
as opposed to masturbation, which would be absurd.
But this parody doesn’t work, because the probabilities
involved in the two cases differ by orders of magnitude: when one of the
millions of sperm cells inseminates an egg and the process of conception
begins, so much work has been accomplished, including the finding of a mate and
the establishment of a pair bond, that the probability is very high that the
fetus would develop into a person--short of a spontaneous or artificial
abortion; biology deals in ceteris paribus laws, after all. Because of
this high probability, a fetus is properly regarded as an early stage of
the fully-formed animal. But masturbation has no such natural connection to
conception; sperm by itself obviously won’t miraculously become a person. The
slogan “pro-choice,” then, concedes this point about the fetus’s special
status, since were the fetus more like sperm by itself, there would be no choice,
in the sense of a hard decision, of what to do with the fetus. It’s only
because a fetus will very probably become a person that the potential parents
face a decision of which future to create, the one that includes or excludes an
additional person. The moral question, then, is whether personhood extends to
this still-early stage of a person.
Consider this analogy. A woman is stabbed to death while she
slumbers. Is that murder? Well, the victim isn’t then actually using the
faculties that make her a person with moral rights, because she’s unconscious
while she sleeps. But because sleep is a normal recurrence for a person, the
probability is extremely high that were she not then stabbed, she would have
awoken and behaved as a semi-rational, free, and conscious person like anyone
else. Granted, the probability is higher in the connection between sleeping and
waking than in the development of a fetus into a full-grown human, since many
factors can intervene between the stages in the latter process. But do the
probabilities here differ by orders of magnitude? Just as there are natural
abortions of fetuses, a person can die naturally in her sleep. Broadly
speaking, though, just as a sleeper will very probably awaken and act as a
person who has moral rights, if anything does, so too a first trimester human
fetus (likewise a part of a process) will very probably become a person, albeit
after a number of years rather than hours. If killing a sleeper is murder, why
isn’t killing a human fetus?
Such are the moral quandaries which are seldom aired in
canned mass media presentations of the abortion issue. But I raise them here
only to get at the aesthetic merit of the pro-choice position. Given that the
masturbation parody of the point about potential personhood is spurious, and
thus that the choice as to whether to abort the fetus is at the very least a
grave decision, if not an act of murder, whether abortion is original or
clichéd, superficially appealing or off-putting, depends on how the choice is
made. If a fetus is aborted because the woman is raped and doesn’t want to bear
the rapist’s child, the act of abortion resists the evolutionary forces that
compel the beastly male to prey on the weak and to spread his genes. That
resistance is novel, a middle finger surprisingly held up to the face of Mother
Nature, a condemnation of natural suffering by a self-aware being and a refusal
to submit to the forces that impose that suffering. That rebellion is of the
essence of modern art.
But suppose, as is more likely the case, the parents
undertake the abortion with little or no appreciation of the situation’s
gravity, aborting the fetus as though undergoing cosmetic surgery on a whim.
Were abortion the tail-end of a process of promiscuous sex,
the act of abortion would be no such creative rebellion against oppressive
forces; on the contrary, the act would conform to one of the most prevalent
patterns in human life, being a technological enabler of a degrading lifestyle,
like birth control. Of course, individualistic societies have social
revolutions which are thought to bestow rights on men and women to do what they
like as long as they don’t hurt anyone else. So the received wisdom in liberal,
modern societies is that if people choose to have a lot of sex, they’re
perfectly entitled. And so they might well morally be were it not for the fact
that morality is bunk, as determined by the same self-destructive naturalistic
perspective that ushers in the social revolutions in question. Looked at
aesthetically, sex is embarrassing, as I argue elsewhere. Those proud feminists
who see no shame in having abortions should be as open about their sex lives to
which birth control and abortion are only accomplices. When someone is proud of
the freedom to abort a fetus, but secretive about the details of his or her sex
life, that person’s suffering from cognitive dissonance. If you’re secretly
ashamed of humping like an animal, like a puppet of mindless genes that perpetuate
themselves as the undead god which is the natural cosmos unfolds to some
inhuman end, you should be just as ashamed of, or at least worried about, the
enablers of sex.
To clarify, my point isn’t remotely that birth control or
abortion should be banned. I’m saying just that abortion can be as conformist
and thus as aesthetically unappealing as sex. When an art critic pans a work of
art, the critic doesn’t try to ban the artist from producing art. Rather, the
critic lays out her reasons and lets others decide what to think. Both moral
and aesthetic values are separate from legal responsibility. Whether action
should be taken against anyone depends on legal institutions which are
intertwined as much with politics as with moral traditions. Moral or aesthetic
values determine how we live our private lives, and so just because an
act is morally or aesthetically dubious doesn’t mean there should be any legal
or other public consequence. On the contrary, the more natural and thus
inhumane a society, the greater the discrepancy between the results of its
legal system and the moral or aesthetic recommendations.
What, though, is my final analysis of the two positions?
Were the pro-life and pro-choice stances reduced to works of art, and were I to
compare them, side-by-side in a gallery, as it were, I’d be unmoved by either
of them since in neither case are the aesthetic ideals unambiguously met.
Neither stance inspires me with confidence that progress can be made in
alleviating our dismal condition. Granted, the pro-choice position is less
objectionable, but mediocre art is closer to failure than to success. One of
the more aesthetically appealing options is asceticism, which bypasses the
whole issue.
Dubious Arguments Against Gay Marriage
What of the current hot topic of gay marriage? Once again,
I’ll summarize the moral arguments and then aesthetically evaluate them. From a
modern perspective, there is no issue of homosexuality or of gay marriage. As
long as gays, lesbians, and others with unusual sexual orientations are
full-fledged people, capable of rational decision-making, and they don’t harm
anyone else by having long-term relationships capable of being legally
regulated, the modern verdict is surely that they have the right to marry.
Opponents say that when homosexuals adopt and raise
children, the children are harmed by not having a female and a male for
parents. This is unlikely, though, since the practice of raising a child in a
household dominated by a single mother and a father is uncommon in human
history; more commonly, children have been raised by the extended family or by
the man’s multiple wives, so that the child’s impression of her parents has
been of a small community rather than just of mother and father figures. For
thousands of years, humans have been serially monogamous or, in most cases,
polygamous. Only in industrially advanced societies, in which communities are
fragmented and families are cut off and dehumanized by their local portals into
the world of electronic hallucinations, beamed from their TVs, computer
screens, and handheld devices, has the Western social breakdown been
rationalized with the notion that a child should be reared primarily by one man
and one woman. Half of Western marriages end in divorce; teens in impoverished
Western communities have unprotected sex at ever-younger ages; and wealthier
individuals follow the European model of virtually arranging marriages to forge
economic alliances and of indulging in affairs out of lust. Conservatives hold
up the 1950s American fantasy of the nuclear family as the solution, whereas
this fantasy is a source of the problem because it runs against the most
powerful instincts.
Another argument against gay marriage is that such marriage
would cheapen the heterosexual institution and further degrade the social
fabric. In advanced Western countries like the US, this argument is made most
frequently by conservatives who live under rocks, unaware of the postmodern
state of affairs in which the younger generations are hyper-skeptical of
everything under the sun, including marriage. When they do get married at all,
rather than just shacking, younger Westerners tend to get married for the legal
benefits, not out of respect for the saccharine metanarratives spun around the
institution of marriage in romantic comedies or in ads for wedding dresses and
so forth. On the contrary, just as Jesus’ alleged birthday has been taken over
by businesses with purely commercial interests, the secular marriage industry
is a thoroughly commercial affair. A marriage is an excuse to throw a huge,
fabulously expensive party, and the materialistic pleasures of weddings would
be enjoyable by the relatives, friends, and associates regardless of the
married couple’s sexual orientation.
No, the true source of opposition to gay marriage is
religious. The prejudice in question derives from the tribal societies that
produced the Bible and the Koran and has memetically made its way to
present-day ignoramuses who know half as much about their own holy scriptures
as does the average atheist. Nevertheless, the fact is that the Torah, Paul’s
letters, and the Koran contain statements that are unequivocally opposed to
homosexual sex. Moreover, the Genesis account of Creation, common to the main
monotheistic religions, allegedly lays out God’s model for human social
relations: God created Adam and then he created Eve to alleviate Adam’s
loneliness (“It is not good for the man to be alone” (Gen.2:18), as Yahweh
says), giving the impression that men and women are supposed to be sexually
intimate just with each other, leaving no room for homosexuality.
The embarrassing weaknesses of this line of argument are as
shockingly numerous as are the stars in a clear night sky. First, as Jack Miles
shows in God: A Biography, the notion that the Hebrew Bible presents God
as a figure who even has a clue what he’s doing from the outset, let alone as
an omniscient mastermind who reveals a flawless life manual for humanity, is
woefully wrongheaded and refuted by nearly every biblical line. Take, for
example, the creation of Adam and Eve. God makes Adam first, then Adam gets
lonely, and God learns from this unsatisfactory result of his initial
handiwork that he’d better improve on what he’s made, and so he creates Eve.
Thus, God didn’t always have in mind the ideal of heterosexual union. Then, of
course, the heterosexual pairing of Adam and Eve proves self-destructive, as
the two get entangled in intrigue with the serpent, and God punishes them for
their evidently flawed relationship, by condemning them to a harsher life. What
this means is that the alleged biblical blueprint for human sexual relations is
nothing of the kind; if anything, what we learn from Genesis is that men and
women shouldn’t live together, that the ideal human relationship--if
there is such a thing--is something God hadn’t conceived of when he first
populated Eden with people.
As for Leviticus, Christians can naturally exploit those
biblical death threats against homosexuals only with extreme prejudice and with
cynical contempt for the bulk of the Bible, since they ignore the comparable
laws against blasphemy, apostasy, witchcraft, adultery, and so on. On the one
hand, Christians say that Jesus’ life and death made Judaism obsolete; on the
other, they cherry-pick useful passages from the Jewish scriptures, purely for
political reasons (in the US, the culture war distracts Republicans from their
Party’s key role in maintaining the American oligarchy). These conservative
Christians are thus much like the Pharisees whom Jesus condemned for being
preoccupied with their position in earthly hierarchies. As for Paul’s letters, I
explain why most Christians hold his teachings to be on equal ground with
Jesus’, in Christian Chutzpah. Jesus was a Gnostic, Essenic hippie who
was opposed to what are now called “family values,” preferring asceticism which
precludes such sexual controversies as gay marriage.
Of course, the more obvious--and for more
consistently-rational people, decisive--objection to the exoteric scriptural
influence on any present-day social phenomenon is that there’s no good reason
whatsoever to defer now to the opinions of Iron Age priests, fishermen, and
raving lunatics. If the Jewish and Christian conservative “thought” is that
social relations were ideal thousands of years ago, which is why we should
model our society on that of the ancient Israelites’, why don’t these conservatives
emigrate from modern nations like Israel or the US to impoverished, premodern
zones like Afghanistan, Pakistan or large parts of India or China? These
so-called conservatives want to have it both ways, taking advantage of the
technoscientific fruits of modernism and longing for archaic social
arrangements. But conservatives are barred from fairly having it thus, since
technoscientific progress doesn’t happen in such tribal, oppressive societies.
Witness much of the Muslim world, which is consistently “conservative,” or
backward-looking, and duly impoverished for lack of modern advances.
Muslim conservatives at least have a modicum of intellectual
integrity on their side when they rage against homosexuality. Mind you, the
refutation of their religious arguments against gay marriage can come in the
form of a finger pointed at the squalor of their living conditions, together
with the following sort of rebuke. “If your social conservatism is so ideal for
humanity, having been revealed by God, why is the more secular and liberal
standard of living in the West so much higher than that in socially
conservative Muslim countries? Why are modern secularists so much happier than
impoverished Muslims who have memorized the Koran and who follow it to the letter,
bringing them little more than a desert wasteland ruled by opulent Middle
Eastern dictators? Sure, these rulers are often supported by secular Western
powers, but the point remains that God would had to have foreseen that strict
Islamic societies would be so easily conquered by modern liberal ones. For all
the problems with modernity, the evidence on the ground is that, if anything,
God favours liberal secularism, not Islamic orthodoxy, which is why Muslims are
currently so frustrated that they riot at the drop of a hat.”
So much for the religious arguments against homosexual
relationships. One final objection before I turn to the aesthetic evaluation:
social conservatives tend to conflate biological with social laws, assuming
both that God created nature, in which case biological functions are normative,
and that homosexuality is biologically dysfunctional. The pseudoscientific
conclusion is that gay marriage is wrong because it’s unnatural. I’ll be brief
with this. First, there’s homosexuality, as well as all manner of sexual
perversions, elsewhere in nature. See, for example, the recently released 1910 records
on the depraved acts of certain penguins. In a moment I’ll come to
the reason for the difference between the repressed conservative’s naïve
outlook on sexuality and the reality of life in the wild. Second, natural laws
aren’t prescriptions and so biological “functions” aren’t normative. The
exoteric theistic conception of the ultimate creative force as personal is
strictly for children or for adults who will be manipulated as children by wily
demagogues. Thus, whatever the natural status of homosexuality, biology has no
implications for how people should live; moreover, exoteric theology is
incompatible with evolutionary biology, especially at the epistemological
level.
Homophobia as an Aesthetic Judgment
What, though, is the natural status of homosexuality? This
question brings me to the main aesthetic point I want to make about gay
marriage. From all of the above, it follows that opposition to gay marriage is
repugnant because the blatant cognitive defects of that opposition indicate our
smallness in the universe; any creatures who could reason so poorly must be
fodder for natural forces, and the social conservative’s arguments against
homosexuality should thus be panned for reminding us of that sad fact about our
position in nature.
But any headway a proponent of gay rights makes by so
refuting the objections is undone by the vacuity of moral argumentation in the
postmodern context. As for the aesthetic standing of homosexuality, then, the
problem is that even though the abnormality of homosexuality doesn’t make this
orientation immoral, this abnormality may leave the impression that this
orientation is ugly. Now, gays can be admired for trying to improve
their sociopolitical situation, for overcoming the stigma which people attach
to homosexuality. Perhaps the notion of Gay Pride is politically useful, to
prevent the abuse of gay people at the hands of so-called homophobic bullies.
Gay Pride parades and the prevalence of gay characters in sitcoms and movies
have helped to normalize those with abnormal sexual orientations. Even were
homophobia a natural and aesthetically telling reaction, this reaction would go
too far were it to lead to the assault or murder of gays--and it has so led. As
I said above, I’m not addressing here the question of legal rights.
Legally, gays can obtain the right to marry if they can empower lawmakers to
write the appropriate laws. My issue here is the aesthetic status of gay
marriage.
The aesthetic problem I see with homosexuality is that the
political strategies that seem necessary to improve the gay person’s precarious
position in heterosexual society run counter to a realistic appreciation of how
homosexuality exacerbates our existential predicament. In evolutionary terms,
there may be a complicated story about how this abnormal sexual orientation is
naturally selected, whether because gays somehow increase the fitness of
certain heterosexual people’s genes or because homosexuality is a byproduct of
some naturally selected trait. Either way, what’s evidently happened is that in
the case of our species, natural forces have thrown together a majority of
heterosexuals and a minority of homosexuals, supplying the former with a
powerful instinct to favour heterosexual unions for the sake of spreading
genes, and this instinct causes the oppression of gays. My question is whether
this natural process is aesthetically pleasing or off-putting, and I suspect
that the answer for most people is the latter.
This doesn’t mean that gays should stop fighting for their
legal rights. But I do think much of the hostility to Gay Pride parades and to
any public flaunting of gay sexuality stems from this negative aesthetic
reaction to gay people’s apparent delusional celebration of their sexuality.
Again, I understand how this celebration can politically empower the gay
community, but it seems to have the unintended consequence of trivializing
homosexuality’s existential significance. In short, gay people protest too
much: when they deliriously revel in their sexuality, they act as though they
had not been cursed, as it were, by mindless yet undead, naturally creative
forces, to square off against biochemically-biased heterosexuals, for precisely
no greater rhyme or reason.
It’s well and good to exercise willpower in the Nietzschean
fashion, to overcome obstacles, putting on a brave face and affirming harsh
facts. But this existential battle requires in the first place a frank,
no-nonsense assessment of where you naturally stand. In all cases, that
assessment causes angst and horror, because our natural situation is absurd and
tragic. How we creatively improve on our existential situation proceeds from
that point, but I fear that those with minority sexual orientations skip the
existential reckoning with their lot and leap to baseless enthusiasm. Perhaps
they’re wise to do so to prevent the victimization of gay people, but all
delusions are naturally off-putting. The paradigmatic delusion is the insane
person’s which indicates a fundamental detachment from reality and an escape
into an imaginary world that doesn’t redeem itself by enabling an uplifting transformation
of the real one. To the extent that Gay Pride resembles that sort of delusion
and gay marriage is made possible by that sociopolitical movement, gay marriage
is marred, aesthetically speaking.
Hi Ben, I am a big admirer of your blog but I have to say I am rather disappointed with this entry. You take for granted the existence of a homosexual gene, even though to this date no evidence of such thing has been found! In your article on the emptiness of postmodern art (and its consumers) you begin by quoting Camille Paglia from a radio interview. I wonder, are you familiar with her work? More specifically, are you familiar with her conception of homosexuality as delineated in her book Sexual Personae?
ReplyDeleteThanks for reading. I do assume there's a genetic basis for homosexuality, but it's more a presumption based on my knowledge that heterosexuality has a genetic basis. It stands to reason that if the genes can produce one kind of sexuality, they can produce another. Still, that implies only that a gay gene is possible. Whether there actually is one is, of course, an empirical question.
DeleteI'm not familiar with Paglia's view on homosexuality, but I googled it and found that she says "No one is born gay. The idea is ridiculous...homosexuality is an adaptation, not an inborn trait." That's actually consistent with the view that homosexuality is genetic, though, since likewise no one is born heterosexual. Babies are obviously asexual, so our sexual identity at the moment of birth is irrelevant. The question is about our genetic potential, something which becomes actualized at puberty and which depends partly on our environment. In the same way, we have a genetic potential to learn a language, but if we're not put in the right environment as children, we can become feral rather than civilized.
In any case, I don't claim to know how homosexuality is caused. What I really want to say in this article is more conditional: even IF homosexuality were entirely genetic, there would still be something wrong about gay pride. The attitude of that pride is as existentially appalling as the happiness of modern folks who should know better. I'm not saying we should be gloomy all the time, but the ways in which nature, the undead frickin god toys with us in its alien, impersonal manner isn't something for us to take pride in. A better kind of pride would be that of the transhsumanist who creatively overcomes nature in something like Nietzsche's sense. Maybe some gay folks do overcome their sexuality, or at least creatively make it their own, but most are lazily proud of what seems to be a genetic quirk or a byproduct of what the genes do best, which is to produce bodies that reproduce themselves to preserve their genetic code.