I’d like to show how a modern form of asceticism which springs from a combination of existentialism and cosmicism relates to some basic philosophical questions about
the natures of fact, meaning, and value.
Fact, Meaning, and Value
What’s the difference between truths and facts? Truth
requires living things whereas facts don’t. There could be a universe of facts
even with no intelligent creatures to appreciate them, but there would be no
truth in a lifeless universe, because truth is a relationship between facts and
what are called symbols or representations of those facts, and symbols are
tools used by living things. To see the difference, suppose there’s a lifeless
world in a distant galaxy, and on that world there’s a range of mountains and
also a lake with waves that lap against a sandy beach. Now suppose that by
chance, as the froth is deposited onto the beach, the froth creates the
spitting image of those mountains, picturing their peaks and valleys as they
would have been seen were someone standing on that beach. In this case, there
would be physical facts of how the mountains are arranged and of their
different sizes, but there would be no truth in the froth’s accidental map of
those facts, because the froth wouldn’t be a tool used by any creature in its
dealings with the world.
Now, from a highly objective perspective, the difference
between the froth’s picture of the mountains, and a person’s thought that one
mountain is larger than another vanishes; in each case, we might say, there’s
just a pair of patterns that happen to match in some respects. The information
in the waves can be mapped onto the information in the mountains, just as the
neural activity in the viewer’s brain could be mapped onto what she’d view,
were she standing on that beach. So maybe neither a fact nor a truth needs any
living user of information, after all; maybe truth is just a certain abstract
correspondence between patterns. This is how some philosophers think of truth,
as an isomorphism between certain sets of data. And indeed, when this match
between patterns is lacking, you don’t have truth and you may even have
falsehood, but this match alone isn’t enough: one of the patterns must be made
up of symbols, and to have symbols you need meaning.
A pattern, like a picture of mountains or the sentence, “One
of those mountains is larger than the other,” carries meaning in relation to
the mountains if that pattern is directed towards them. But what is it for one
thing to be thusly about something? I
think we can answer this by comparing symbols to something like guidelines on
the tarmac used by a pilot to land the plane. The lines hook up with the pilot
in the cockpit (through his eyes and his brain) and direct the plane to its
landing position, which is where the pilot wants to go. In the same way, mental
symbols--our thoughts, feelings, images, and other mental states--facilitate
our negotiations with the outside world. They do this by their useful
associations with other mental states, as in a train of thought, and by their
access to our motor responses, so that we can intelligently move our body,
guided by that inner map. Mental symbols have those features because they’re
made up of highly interconnected brain states which, of course, have executive
control over the body.
So what is it for a symbol to mean something? This kind of
meaning has at least two aspects. First, if you put certain symbols together
under certain circumstances, such as the time and place of their occurrence,
their directedness towards something adds up to a truth relation, as I’ve said, or else lives up to some other ideal,
as in the case of motivational symbols, which I’ll come to in a moment. By
itself, this first criterion of meaning is relatively trivial since, as the
above thought experiment shows, any patterns might match by chance or else
might be interpreted as matching by some arbitrary hermeneutic principle. Second,
though, even when they’re not so put together, as in the case of isolated words
that aren’t used to form a sentence, symbols guide the symbol-user’s use of that to which the symbols are
directed, such as the referent. The semantic relation, then, is like a path
extending from the symbol-user to something that might be used, and the path
features relevant tools that give the user options in dealing with what the
symbol potentially directs the user toward. Again, these other tools consist of
the associated symbols, each taking the user down a slightly different path,
and also of the symbol’s access to the user’s body, which allows action to be
intelligently guided. A symbol’s reference to something, then, is invisible
because that meaning is a set of potential
relationships between symbol-user and the referent. Indeed, symbols tend to be
public property, so the referent isn’t just an idiosyncratic interpretation of
what’s out there, like the mountain range, but the conventionally relevant
information pertaining to mountains in general.
If a mental symbol is a tool, like a shovel, is it just the
symbol that has this one-way relation to something, called in this case the
symbol’s meaning? In fact, all tools are likewise directed towards something in
what we can call an active-passive relationship. Just like a fact-related
symbol (a concept or belief), we use a shovel to achieve some goal in the real
world. Like a symbol, a shovel presents us with a way of interacting with parts
of the world, depending on the shovel’s capacities. A shovel is normally used
to dig holes, but it can be used for other purposes as well; moreover, like a
symbol, a shovel can be misused: for example, a shovel would make for a poor
toothpick. Just as the thought of shovels presents the thinker with an array of
options, as the relevant information streams across her inner vision like the
Terminator’s cynical assessments of its surroundings, an actual shovel triggers
the user’s relevant know-how when the use of the shovel becomes second nature
to her. (On this point, see Andy Clark’s book, Natural-Born Cyborgs, and the philosophical theory of the extended
mind.) So the opportunity to apply a symbol in various potential ways directs
the user to the world, while other, non-semantic tools direct the user to something
in a similar sort of active-passive relationship (the user does things to the
used).
What gives neural activity or the word “shovel,” but not an
actual shovel, semantic content? Concepts and linguistic symbols are digital rather than analogue, meaning that their physical or biological characteristics
are irrelevant to the user, whereas a shovel’s size, shape, and so on are
crucial to the user’s ability to carry out the shovel’s function. True, as I
said, mental representations can drive behavior only by physically tapping into
the brain’s motor center, but the user is typically quite unaware of the
mechanisms involved. When you think of shovels, you’re aware only of a rush of cognitive
associations, images, memories, and feelings. But when you pick up a shovel,
your know-how consists of your experience with the shovel’s physical
properties: for example, you have to learn which is the business end, how to
bend your back to get enough leverage, and so on. A non-symbolic tool’s
active-passive relation to what’s used by means of the tool is thus less
ghostly, as it were, than the abstract relation between a symbol and what the
symbol is about. But note that the more complex the technology, the more the
lay user is inclined to assign the equivalent of a semantic relation between
the machine and whatever’s acted upon by the machine. That is, when we’re
mystified as to how a machine works, we treat the fulfillment of its function
as a kind of magic, attributing the machine’s effectiveness to ghostly forces
or to angels or other spirits. For example, a computer’s electrical connections
to its peripherals might as well be digital, semantic relations, since our
bodies hardly come into contact with most of the computer’s parts, just as
we’re mostly ignorant of how the neural basis of a thought works.
This second aspect of meaning is, of course, a pragmatic one, and it can be used to
distinguish facts from truth. Again, truth is a match between two patterns,
where one of those patterns consists of symbols, and symbols are tools that guide
action, helping the user to succeed in some fashion (to satisfy certain wants
or needs). By contrast, facts are how things are either before they’re so used
or when something is considered objectively, independent of any such particular
use. For example, physical facts of mountains pertain to what mountains would
be like even were there no such thing as symbols or their users. Facts
pertaining to artificial kinds, like toys, clothing, or symbols themselves,
which wouldn’t exist without symbol-users, are what these kinds are like
regardless of any independent interpretation. In the case of a highly
subjective item, like an art work, there may be no facts of the matter but just
a host of symbolic pathways leading to no common ground and just connecting
symbol-users as they trade their interpretations.
This way of distinguishing facts and truths raises the
question of normativity, since the
practical aspect of symbols entails that some uses of symbols are more
successful than others. Thus, the symbols that relate creatures to facts depend
on a separate, more obviously normative class of symbols, which we can call
desires. Suppose someone wants to climb a mountain, but instead of acquiring
useful gear for the endeavor, the climber uses a shovel to dig his way
underneath the mountain, saying “If I dig deep enough, I might just climb this
mountain.” In this case, there’s a mismatch between the person’s goal and his
means of achieving it. One of these means is his inner, cognitive tool, his
mental representation of mountains, which differs strangely from the standard
concept of mountains. If your goal is to stand on top of the mountain, you need
a useful mental representation to guide your planning and your actions. And if
you fail miserably in achieving your goal, there’s a greater chance that you
lack the relevant concept in the first place. Moreover, the more limited a
species’ goals, that is, the simpler its habits and its life cycle, the fewer
symbols its members possess.
The pragmatic aspect of meaning, then, is normative, because
actions depend on intentions, and intentions spring from character or from disposition,
which consists of a mix of virtues and vices, according to an ethical or
aesthetic ideal for judging such things. Instrumentally speaking, the
efficiency of tool-use can be evaluated just in case the tool achieves the goal;
that is, the tool’s value can be relative just to the specific desire, so that
the use is neutral with respect to any ideal that governs the value of desires
themselves. For example, a murderer’s use of a weapon can be more or less
effective in achieving his goal even though that goal is evil. But then there’s
the deeper rightness or wrongness of our goals. Goals motivate us to act and
thus drive our use of fact-directed symbols, charging them with meaning. Moreover,
goals range from those which are unique to each person to those of wider and
wider social networks, such as family, country, and the whole set of language
speakers, including the long dead ones whose past experiences help shape the
present meaning of words; on top of those, there are the species-wide instincts
we inherit from evolution. Each of these motivations pressures the symbol-user
to take up symbols and walk down the path that leads to some use of the
referent. The more general the motivation, the more well-worn the path and the
greater the impact on the symbol’s particular meaning. For example, the lay concept
of mountains includes just the stereotypical information that’s useful for
fulfilling most people’s potential use of mountains, including the facts that a
mountain is an abrupt rising of the earth’s surface, rising to an altitude
greater than that of a hill, which amount to a warning that you shouldn’t
trifle with a mountain. After all, a mountain has many other properties, but
only the practically relevant ones, given most people’s interests, are picked
out by the standard concept of mountains. The word “mountain” has several
senses, though, and the context of the particular speaker’s interest will
decide in which sense the word or thought is intended.
Our mental tools can be divided roughly into beliefs and
desires. Beliefs aim towards facts, and the aiming is a matter of the belief’s
usefulness in achieving some potential objectives. The concept of mountains
contains information that helps us deal with mountains, and this information
includes the concept’s associations with relevant concepts, such as those of
hills, rugged terrain, avalanches, and so on. By contrast, desires aim towards
not something in the actual world, but towards a possibility we’d prefer to be
factual. You can think about this in terms of possible worlds. If a belief is
true, it usefully connects the believer to part of the actual world, and if the
belief is false it connects the believer to a possible, counterfactual world.
Some misuses of symbols can be counterproductive or useful, depending on whether
the symbol is used in a lie or in a comforting delusion. Now, a desire connects
the symbol-user not just to any possible world, but to a preferred one, and the preference derives from a value, ideal, or a
vision of how the facts should be. Typically, a desire motivates the user to take
some action to conform the actual world with that vision, but some desires,
like hopes, don’t have that effect.
In any case, a
belief, or an objective fact-directed symbol, is supposed to live up to the
ideal of truth, as it were, while a desire, or a preferred fact-directed
symbol is governed by some other ideal. And the pragmatic aspect of beliefs
connects beliefs to desires: we use beliefs to guide our actions, because we
prefer a certain state of the world, and beliefs help us produce or maintain that
state.
The Meaning of Asceticism
The normative aspect of meaning raises three issues that
will lead us to consider existentialism and cosmicism. First, is there a goal
presupposed by all human symbol-use, which is partly what enables us to
distinguish between symbols and non-symbols, and if so, what’s that goal?
Second, assuming there is such a goal, is the corresponding notion of success
deficient according to a higher ideal? Third, how can we explain the emergence
of normativity (of values, ideals, and so on) without committing the naturalistic
fallacy?
As I said, the particular context of each use of a symbol
may affect its meaning, but there’s an underlying role of symbols, which is the
biological one. Our mental categories are tools used by the genes to manipulate
us to survive, reproduce, and transmit the genetic information to the next
generation. I discuss one such method of control in Cosmicism and Technology, where I point out that
the source of our anthropomorphic projections onto alien nature, which usefully
delude us, sparing us the ravages of existential angst, is the associational
aspect of our neural nets. We understand something by relating it to what’s
more familiar, and we’re most familiar with how we appear to ourselves. Thus, one
such underlying purpose of symbol-use is to protect the genotype, by deluding
the genes’ host: we instinctively and naively presume the world is personal and
humane. As in all biological purposes or functions, though, the appearance of intelligent
design is a trick of human perception. All of nature is mysteriously neither alive
nor lifeless, but undead like a zombie abomination. What this means
is that the use of people by our genes
is merely apparent; there’s no ghost in the machine, but spiritless matter is
more active than any known biological life, having mindlessly evolved the whole
universe.
Another such underlying purpose of symbol-use derives from
reason: we play with symbols in a social game of climbing to the apex of our
dominance hierarchy, thus again earning privileged positions for our progeny
and our genetic lineage, and distracting ourselves with those ulterior
pseudomotives instead of taking a good look at our existential predicament.
Reason evolved as a tool for Machiavellian manipulation, for spin-doctoring and
the rhetorical art of persuasion, for the sake of protecting our personal
brand, that is, our status in the tribe. Thus, our typical thought patterns are
rife with biases and fallacies, as cognitive science shows.
The answer to the first question, then, is that there is
such an underlying purpose, and it’s well-symbolized by the fiction of the machines’
self-serving maintenance of the matrix’s virtual reality. In effect,
the primary users of symbols are the genes and the other forces of natural
selection, which build our bodies including our instincts to think and react in
ways that further the overriding process which is the evolution of biological
life. How is this relevant to the meaning of our thoughts? Well, if I’m right
and meaning is like the line on the tarmac that guides a pilot’s landing of the
plane--except that a thought is connected to a fact only by a ghostly version
of such a line, namely by the opportunity for the symbol-user to act on that
fact, afforded by the thought’s ability to control the user’s body--then a
symbol is directed towards something mainly by our naturally evolved
opportunities. The force of natural selection is like a fleet of machines that
digs a maze of paths leading from each of us to various ports of call, and most
of our activity in life is confined to that pre-existing infrastructure. Our
opportunities to influence the world are naturally limited by how we tend to
think and by what our bodies can do, which limits are culturally and biologically
set. Within those limits, we can choose to take one path or another, as we put
our symbols together in different combinations to suit our parochial interests;
we can modify the pre-established landscape, changing the meaning of our
symbols as cultures and languages develop, digging new pathways and opening up
new opportunities. But the main driving force of symbol-use, which sets symbols
apart from non-symbols, by giving symbols meaning and thus a causal role in the
symbol-user’s behavior, is that of natural selection, which is to say that
there’s a foreign zombie hand reaching into everyone’s head, infecting us with
the plague of undeadness and coercing us to shamble along well-worn roads.
As to the second question, readers of this blog shouldn’t be
surprised to read that indeed I think there are higher ideals and thus what we
might call a transhuman use of symbols, that is, a way that truly sets us apart
from most animal species. Most thinking is done directly or indirectly in the
service of our zombie masters, the micro machines and environmental forces that
build our bodies; these thought patterns include the politically correct myths
and conventions that distract and delude us, appealing to our vanity even as
the narratives act as blinders and leashes around our necks. For thousands of
years, though, there’s been the spiritual, mystical, ascetic alternative,
reformulated in existentialist terms after the World Wars. This esoteric culture for
detached, angst-ridden outcasts, misfits, seekers, and mentally unbalanced
freaks of nature is governed by anti-natural ethical or aesthetic standards
that put us at odds with the natural world and thus with ourselves. In
religious terms, the goal is to escape our cosmic prison, what I call the
decaying corpse of the undead god, and this liberation is
accomplished by saying “No!” a thousand times to natural impulses, to abstain
from many biological and mainstream cultural endeavours, to malfunction, as it
were, condemning nature as a monstrosity and throwing a wrench into the works.
Ascetic, existential rebellion against natural processes is ethical, because it calls for the
ultimate virtues of self-knowledge and integrity. Perhaps more importantly,
this rebellion is aesthetic in that
it amounts to any creature’s supremely creative act. You might be wondering, if
nature is an undead monstrosity inhabited by mini undead monsters, how could
one way of life be better than another? Surely, then, it’s all just rot and
decay, the spiritless shuffling along of physically interacting chunks of
matter, yielding more and more complex patterns of monstrosity, from molecules
to galaxies to alternate dimensions and universes. But this is the point: one
such emergence seems to be nature’s ability to deny itself, to look upon itself
in horror, through the mystic’s eyes, and to reject our position as instruments
in Mother Nature’s experiment on this planet. Plato interpreted the rise of
abstraction in normative terms, so that the more general the phenomenon the
better it is, with mathematical objects, for example, being better than
particular physical things which he saw as copies of their categories. I would
replace his measure of abstraction with that of complexity, and instead of calling the increase in emergent
complexity generally good, I’d call it beautiful
solely in the sense that an emergent phenomenon is original and thus not
clichéd. There should be no illusion that what’s new is necessarily
progressive. As John Gray says in Black
Mass, that linear, teleological way of telling history is an inheritance
from Zoroastrianism. But the vertical dimension of Plato’s hierarchy remains in
a measure of complexity and thus of natural originality and beauty. (See Aesthetic Morality.)
The point is that whereas slavish adherence to our biofunctions
is conformist, ascetic rebellion is creative and thus aesthetically superior as
a life option. In terms of symbol-use, the ascetic goal of detaching, to some
extent, from natural processes invests the ascetic’s symbols with an ironic
sort of self-destructive meaning, since the ascetic uses symbols to formulate
paradoxes (in myths and parables) that reveal how reason traps and curses us;
alternatively, the mystic may attempt to abstain from thinking, to free her
mind from the matrix of biologically- and culturally-imposed virtual reality. The
mystical ascetic or rebellious existentialist creates a higher plain in the
pattern of her renunciation, which is to say that any degree of asceticism is
more creative than conformity to processes that are explainable in strictly
lower-level terms, such as biological ones. Granted, rebellion against nature
conforms to the metaphysical pattern of nature’s evolution of emergent levels
of complexity, and the universe does regularly deny itself, in a sense, by
creatively destroying parts of itself, as in the case of a black hole that
swallows star systems. But the emergence of what Schopenhauer calls the denial
of the will to live raises the stakes, because this denial occurs within the
undead god’s crown jewel which is the brain, the most complex, improbable, and
thus original and aesthetically praiseworthy object.
There’s more to be said, though, in comparing the conformist
and the artistically creative cultures. There is, I think, a tragedy in the machine’s simulation of a
supernatural spirit, and the emotional power of this tragedy in the case of
rebellion against nature adds to the beauty of antiheroic life. What I mean is
that the best mythical way of thinking of the world’s creation, to which we’re
led by our social instinct which compels us to personify the impersonal, is to
assume that God became corrupted by his absolute power and destroyed himself
out of horror at his self-reflection, creating the universe literally out of
his miraculously undying, mindlessly creative body. (See God’s Self-Destruction.) That’s just a speculative myth,
of course, although I think it’s more psychologically plausible than the
commonplace Creation myths. But the aesthetic point is that surely there can be
no greater tragedy than such an act of divine suicide, a tragedy which
Christianity effectively bastardizes and whitewashes. There’s honour in the
idea of a great person’s vindication after she falls, even if that vindication
is tragic, given that the only way of improving her situation is to destroy
herself. I take this to be the best interpretation of the idea of monotheism.
(As to whether God “exists” or once “existed,” that’s merely a childishly
exoteric question. See From Theism to Cosmicism.)
An atheist is free to say, “Who cares?”--except that even an
atheist is stuck with a human brain that can’t help but rally around something
she holds to be sacred, such as human nature, which she instinctively
anthropomorphizes just as the theist does with respect to the First Cause. If
the atheist can have her fun with secular humanism, glorifying human nature and
our scientific progress despite the fact that according to Darwinism we’re a
species of enslaved zombie, the atheist shouldn’t begrudge the mystic her entertaining
speculations about the ultimate cause. (Of course, when the emotional power of myths
drives people to evil behavior, as in the case of monotheistic religions and
scientistic cults like Nazism, the evil-doers should be spanked like naughty children
for failing to distinguish between reality and their bedtime stories.)
Anyway, the relevance of this tragic Creation myth is that human
asceticism is like an echo of that ultimately moving event, of the literal
death of God. The idea is that an omniscient and omnipotent being sees and does
everything, but that instead of settling into the life of an insipid father
figure, God would have become cynical and repulsed by all possibilities except for
the most radical one of escaping his godhood through a form of ironically-creative
self-destruction. Such would be the fate of pure spirit, of the life we naively
imagine we possess. Instead, we’re mere machines playing at life, zombies that mistake
our twitches and moans for noble gestures. The
best we can do is to simulate a novel level of reality. Our experiences of
ourselves and of the outer world are in fact models, which is to say
simplifications of what we encounter. So too we undead things can pretend that
we were all along meant to be virtuous or beautiful; we can choose to adopt anti-natural
ideals that don’t figure so easily in the abominable evolutionary process,
which births new life by means of mass executions of all previous generations.
The greatest of our simplifications is surely our simulation
of God’s tragic denial of the will to life. This calls not for suicide in the
sense of the total extinction of life, since this would cut the rebellion
short, whereas our foe deserves to witness, as it were, the prolongation of the
act of extending our middle finger, just as the most probable God wouldn’t have
replaced himself with nothing at all, but would have transformed himself into
the mindlessly creative behemoth which is the natural universe. Likewise, the
ascetic who detaches from the more egregious biological and politically correct
processes sees herself as the shell she is, which frees her to become something
new: a creature that dares to mimic the deity's primordial act of coming honourably
face to face with the ultimate horror of its existential predicament and then
creatively transcending that horror. God would have done this by the ultimate
act of rebellion, by slaying the Almighty and exchanging his supernatural
personage with a natural and thus entropically doomed, yet curiously creative
and thus undying corpse. And a mere animal can do this by imitating that
pattern to some degree, at least, participating in the ancient ascetic
tradition.
Finally, I want to ask how all of this ethical and aesthetic
talk avoids the naturalistic fallacy.
Recall that this fallacy is to say that a prescription of what we ought to do
might follow logically just from a description of how things are. There is
supposed to be, then, a dichotomy between facts and values. But Darwinism
removes this dichotomy, just as it renders obsolete the naïve distinction
between life and non-life. Instead, there are just simulations of life by
spiritless things which are thus, intuitively speaking, neither living nor lifeless
but undead. If spiritless matter can accomplish the work of the evidently-absent
God, creating all natural forms by mindless evolution and complexification, the
barrier between the logically separate spheres of facts and values is
shattered. In a pantheistic scheme, questions of value arise not just for
creatures who are alive in the technical, biological sense, but for the whole
universe which likewise plays at being alive, albeit with no brain and thus
with no mind or intelligence. Hence the Eastern mystic’s judgment that the whole
apparent world is a hideous prison, a diabolical system of manufacturing and
tricking creatures, thus increasing the amount of suffering. Sure, these
ethical and aesthetic judgments are subjective, but they’re likewise subjective
when applied to human patterns of behavior; that is, these judgments all depend
not just on the observed patterns but on the cognitive tools brought to bear in
interpreting them. We instinctively personify what we observe, because we’re
social mammals; thus, when we philosophize, attempting to make a coherent whole
out of scientific knowledge and our everyday experience, we mythologize and
rationalize our vain anthropomorphic projections.
At any rate, the naturalistic fallacy presupposes a
Cartesian dualism between facts and values. That dualism is no longer tenable.
Note, though, that those who avail themselves of this monistic response to the charge
of having committed that fallacy, are all the closer to existential cosmicism,
since the metaphysical oneness of everything provides a basis for condemning
what Descartes called the entirely lifeless machine of the material world. With
that judgment in mind, some sort of rebellion against nature is in order. Hence
the need for a viable--as opposed to crudely pseudoscientific or childishly
theistic--postmodern religion.
The Philosophy of Existential Cosmicism
To summarize, there are facts, symbols and values. The
metaphysical facts of nature are horrifying, and our existential predicament is
that reason curses us to discover them and thus to suffer debilitating angst
and alienation. Because we have a biological job to do, the forces of natural
selection save most of us from that fate, by putting blinders around our minds,
designing our bodies to prefer the straight and narrow path along which we act
as clownish hosts of our genes. We tend to use mental symbols to bind us to
that path and to help us succeed in evolutionary terms while traversing it,
surviving, reproducing, raising a family, and climbing the social ladder. But there’s
another, anti-natural path, which calls for a higher class of interests and
ideals, and by “higher” I mean to say elevated in the hierarchy of complexity,
which earns that level aesthetic praise. The ideal that motivates most
symbol-use and intelligent behavior derives from the undead god whose forces of
natural selection are set along the absurd path of maintaining an endless flow
of genes into the future. Most of us adopt that ideal, that zombie moan of our
monstrous god, as sacred, even if we rationalize such primitive nature worship
with a thousand popular delusions. Some of us choose, instead, to sacrifice their happiness the way the living God would have been forced to, leaving for
dead the repellent parts of themselves, and rebelling--however futilely and to
whatever degree--against the natural order. The ascetic ideal, then, is the aesthetically-inviting
opportunity to create an original level of reality, a cosmic play of rebellion in
which nature’s crowning achievement, the clever ape, tears to shreds the
monstrous hand that feeds it.
Your call to existential rebellion is based on the idea of facts and the horror they provoke.
ReplyDeleteWhat exactly are these facts? Or to be more more precise, what makes an idea a fact?
I've always seen existentialism as a necessary response to the absence of certainty, or facts as you call them, so naturally I'm interested how you combine existentialism and the belief in certainties.
Thanks for those questions. The facts are those of naturalism and cosmicism (we're finite, contingent animals, largely irrational, unconscious, and not so free; there's no God, nor any guarantee of ultimate justice or meaning; we're cosmically homeless and alienated). (By the way, for my next article I'll be writing more about those facts when I critique Ray Brassier's nihilism.) What I take from existentialism, among other things, is the ideal of personal authenticity. So the philosophy is called "existential cosmicism," and the facts have to do with the cosmicism side (cosmicism assumes philosophical naturalism), while ethics come in with existentialism.
DeleteSo the picture is this: science presents us with greatly-distressing facts, causing most people to delude themselves with fantasies to escape from dealing responsibly with them. The nobler response is the existentialist's: to accept the facts by way of creatively overcoming them. So overcoming something isn't the same as running away from it.
You might be right that uncertainty plays some role in existential discussions. Certainly, Sartre emphasized our absolute freedom and thus the lack of any precondition of our choices, so the life we choose is highly uncertain until we choose it; that's why we alone are responsible for our life. I don't take on board that view of freedom, since his phenomenology is solipsistic. I begin with the objective, science-centered worldview as the worst-case scenario.
Anyway, another existential feeling is angst, which includes a kind of uncertainty about what we should do, and I think science is a great cause of that uncertainty. But science is just the messenger, so the source of our uncertainty--about our myths and delusions--is the world of facts that science discovers.
Hi Ben; this is by far my favorite web journal out there, and I am constantly thinking about your writings and bringing your ideas up with both my students and my training partners, hashing them out with my chavrusas, etc.
ReplyDeleteOne question re a line in this article of which I am having trouble grokking the meaning: re Naturalistic Fallacy, you write: "If spiritless matter can accomplish the work of the evidently-absent God, creating all natural forms by mindless evolution and complexification, the barrier between the logically separate spheres of facts and values is shattered."
I ask, why does it necessarily follow that the barrier between facts/values shatters due to spiritless matter being able to accomplish/create all natural forms by complexification? Is it because there no longer can be a clear "ought" that follows from how things "are", because there are infinite/all possible "are's", and thus an infinite number of possibilities for "ought"?
Was wondering if you can explain what you mean a bit more, in this regard. Thanks.
And on a side-note, in my own private writings I have often portrayed the Torah character of Cain as the *actual* hero of the symbolic narrative (and, in a sense, of the Universe), for Cain recognized (perhaps as a consequence/inheritance of his mom and the serpent (the other big hero!) accessing the Tree of Knowledge) and recoiled from the ugly horror of "reality" (physical laws, natural rules, God's rules, the existential condition, usw.) and angrily *rebelled* against and *repudiated* "God" (I'm operating symbolically here), smashing the Reality imposed upon him with the rock of radical repudiation.
Good-naturedly wondering if your adopted surname is a reflection of any thematically-similar musings. Once again, our compliments on your thoughtful and original writings.
J.D. Rosemont
Thanks very much, J.D. I'm delighted to hear my ideas might be bandied about in a classroom somewhere, although I worry a bit about spoiling the innocence of youth.
DeleteRegarding Judaism, you might be interested in an article I'm planning to post in a week or two, about the relations between mythopoetic thought, the existential (omega man) aspect of Jewish monotheism, and the re-enchantment aspect of scientific objectification. It will tie together a number of my ideas, I think, and the jumping-off point is Frankfort's book where he introduces the idea of mythopoetic thought.
Regarding that line from this article, I was trying to say that pantheism is fit for posthumans who look past apparent dualisms and have some third way of seeing both living and nonliving things, which I see only through a dark glass. I use the metaphor of undeadness to try to capture what it means for nature to simulate creativity.
Does nature consist merely of facts, which are the outputs of objective reflection? In that case, values, ideals, and morality are unreal or at best illusory. Or is it mind-independent facts that are unreal and mental categories that are primary? That's the old dualism which goes back to Descartes and beyond.
I'm exploring a pantheistic myth/metaphysical system which does away with that dichotomy. For example, in my recent article on humanization and objectification, I stress that our capacity for objectivity nevertheless puts a human face on what we objectify. Also, there's my take on technology in the article on the fact-value dichotomy, which talks about the meaning of our replacement of the wilderness of natural facts with our artificial, humanized environments.
As for the cursed rebel wanderer Cain, the name does seem appropriate to my writing, doesn't it! Mind you, I don't think the Bible says why he killed Abel. I touch on the themes here in "Is the Devil a Hero?"