Some of the earliest personifications of nature were the
projections of God as a king and a lawmaker. In prehistoric, low-tech
societies, the most important inventions, after language and the ego
themselves, were the hunting tribe and then the Neolithic village. Laws were
needed to maintain the social order and ancient theists and animists understood
the rest of the world to be similarly regulated by hidden personages. The
supernatural world was just an invisible social order in which the absolute
ruler and his aristocrats and entourage created and governed the natural world
much as we construct our microcosmic societies, that is, our tribes, civilizations, empires, and so on, as
oases from the wilderness.
That kind of personalizing cognition became obsolete with
modern objectification. We still habitually personify
ourselves and each other, because we’re too proud to consider ourselves
animals, but the fictional characters of the gods died in importance for most
of the modern intelligentsia. Instead of a remote social realm, there were just
more and more objects, as scientists discovered; for example, the lights in the
sky turned out to be stars, not gods. Coincidentally or not, the pace of Western
technical innovations quickened with the Renaissance and then with Industrial
Revolution, just as modern scientists from Copernicus to Newton, and Darwin to
Einstein used their new methods of discovery and mathematical description to
model nature as a machine. The philosophy of deism prevented the masses that
still depended on the old gods for their sanity and morality, from revolting
against science for having depersonalized the universe and banished the gods to
nowhere. For a time, informed people could think of the universe as a
self-regulating machine designed by a great architect. But given the modern
biologist’s mechanical explanation of the design of organisms and the quantum physicist’s
account of the creation of universes from chaos, the cosmicist implications of
modern objectification are logically inescapable. People are outgrowths of
impersonal systems; we’re not metaphysically fundamental and so we ought to
feel alienated from automated nature. Luckily, most people can’t hope to follow
the scientist’s logic nor are they interested in following it, in the first
place, because even as science undermines our comforting fictions, applied
science is a cornucopia of goodies which distracts us from the ghastliness of
the hand that feeds us.
As modern scientists came to see nature in its corporeal
splendor, through their telescopes and microscopes, they depersonalized
themselves, developing the scientific institutions and using experiments to circumvent
their prejudices and the prevailing dogmas, to explain what they saw. Thus, the world’s undeadness came to match
that of nature’s heralds. Of course, scientists were prone to the same
animalistic tendencies as the rest of us: they bickered, harbored resentments,
and competed for power in their dominance hierarchies; some even worked
feverishly on theological problems, as in the case of Isaac Newton. But the
scientific methods themselves coldly detach hypotheses from such messy social
contexts, algorithmically sorting adequate from useless models. In short,
science became a social machine to mirror the natural systems that were measured
with ever greater exactness by the extended senses in the laboratories.
Engineering and the Undeadness of Natural Machines
Two kinds of scientific worldviews emerged from those
revolutions, which I’ll call the engineer’s and the mathematician’s. These
worldviews aren’t scientific theories, but tendencies in science to interpret
theories according to different naturalistic assumptions. Moreover, the point
isn’t that all professional engineers and mathematicians line up on one side or
the other, but that these two flavors of naturalism arise especially out of
those two disciplines. That is, I’m talking about two types of naturalism that derive
from certain attitudes among scientists, born from different kinds of
scientific work. There’s some overlap between engineering and mathematics, but
these groups are also divided by different mindsets and cultures. So, then, the
engineering-centered picture takes for granted the technologies that provide scientists with the data needed to
formulate their hypotheses. In addition, the engineer appreciates the work that goes into scientific
explanation, including the economic and political systems needed to separate
Church from State in modern Europe, which allowed early modern scientists to
work with less and less fear of persecution. Finally, the engineer’s sort of
naturalism is pragmatic in that the
engineer is inspired by the power of natural causes to determine their effects
and thus he takes science to be the means by which we control nature, in turn. Incidentally,
engineering-centered scientists are overwhelmingly male.
In this world picture, then, nature is objectified, to be
sure, but it’s also understood as a creative
process. Just as the engineer builds things, so too natural forces form
matter into systems that develop more complex levels of organization. Time is
regarded as real in this world picture and the scientist’s task is to
understand how natural mechanisms work within their cycles. This is not a
teleological worldview, though, since no one mentally represents the stages of
these processes—besides the scientist, of course, who has no part in setting
most natural processes in motion. Moreover, there’s no real end within a
natural cycle and thus no goal achieved by the work of natural forces and
systems. Any end of a natural process is an artifact of a way of conceptualizing
and thus simplifying the phenomenon, as opposed to being objective or real. We
merely lack an interest in, or are unable to discover what happens after a
certain point, which leads us to speak of beginnings or ends in nature. For
example, we refer to a star’s birth or to a planet’s death, but the matter and
energy in those cases merely change form.
Indeed, strictly speaking, there are no natural processes, in so far as a process is a
systematic series of actions directed towards some end. To speak of the process
of natural selection, for example, is to use a potentially misleading metaphor.
Natural systems aren’t really engineers that plan ahead to achieve some goal,
of course. Nevertheless, these systems do evolve and create other systems, and
so the engineering-centered picture is of an undead, “decaying” world. The
zombie comparison is yet another metaphor, but at least it doesn’t tempt us to assume
the personal connotations of “natural process.”
And yet the fact that natural mechanisms accomplish work,
that nature is zombielike in that it creates orders of complexity like a living
engineer, while lacking any vitality including any power of forethought raises
a curious question of cosmic eschatology. After all, wasn’t there an absolute
beginning in the Big Bang and won’t there be some ultimate end, after all, such
as a heat death of everything, depending on the universe’s geometry? There may
be no real beginnings or ends within
nature except those we posit to suit our interest in understanding parts of the
whole, but the universe seems necessarily self-contained in so far as
it’s scientifically understood. Objective reality has limits and definite
forms, including a finite number of dimensions. If, then, the universe has a
beginning and an end, can we speak of nature as having an objective purpose
and of all of the changes within the universe as steps towards some
inevitable endpoint?
To be sure, the process would be undead and without
intrinsic value, given the atheism implicit in any sort of modern naturalism. But
the question remains, in short, whether there’s such a thing as fate within this engineer’s vision of
nature. Again, not if the concept of fate entails an agent to prescribe events,
as it did in ancient Greek thought, but perhaps that myth-making has always been a way
for social beings like us to feel comfortable with the world’s alien pseudo-agency. We intuit that as the seasons always return and even as the
constellations resume their positions in the sky after passing through their
orbits, so too all of nature must be endless and ideal, to match our archetype
of paradise. That comforting image has been rendered childish and idle in light
of modern techniques of objectification. Still,
the objective world isn’t devoid of power or creativity. And where there are
such propensities, there too are pseudo-processes and the spawning of an undead
cosmos that marches to oblivion. All
transitions within nature, then, seem like so many doomed protestations against
the fate of any undead thing, which is to decay and collapse under the weight
of its blasphemy.
Time is king in
this picture of nature, being the beat to which all things march, and they
march in lockstep to natural law. Causality,
then, is the chain that drags all systems into the obliteration at the end of
time. David Hume argued that causality is unreal, that we project that occult
power onto nature, whereas we’re empirically justified in speaking only of the
regularities we strictly observe. That is, all we see is one sort of event
repeatedly following another sort, under certain conditions. We don’t observe
the one sort forcing the other to happen, so there’s no such thing as causal
connection, as far as we can tell just from our senses. Unluckily for the
empiricist, we needn’t rely just on our senses. Were we to do so and to stop
thinking about we perceive, there would be no need for philosophical skepticism
since there would have been no ascent of human civilization to support the
speculations that elite mammals are liable to toy with in their decadence. Indeed,
were we to go on just what our senses show us, we’d have no reason to think
that the lights in the night sky are actually stars that are much larger than
our planet, nor any reason to think our planet is a sphere (unless we somehow manage
to see all sides of the Earth at once from outer space). Moreover, there would
be no such thing as rational justification, in the first place, so it wouldn’t
matter what we believe, because neither do we observe any belief’s being better than another. Indeed, if we strip
away our cognitive faculties, there would be no sense at all in our sensations,
no conceptual simplifications for the sake of understanding, but just a chaotic
blur of unprocessed sensory information.
Thus, as Kant explained (although not exactly in these
terms), to understand what we perceive we employ our categories and metaphors
and other mental programs. As I put it elsewhere, we humanize the
phenomenon even as we objectify it. And so we posit causality as well as gods,
disposing of the latter without having to do the same with the former, because
there are many epistemic criteria available. But the point is that causality casts a Gnostic pallor if we think of
the natural order as a series of evolutions that brings the universe that much
further to an end that negates all prior events. In this world picture in
which time is paramount, because what’s most real for the engineering-centered
naturalist is creative work and power, it will be exactly as if there had been
no mighty, sublime universe, when everything ends in some nearly unimaginable
cataclysm. There will be no one then to tell the tale, no runner to pass the
torch; the sun will rise no more and all will be lost. If there are causes and
effects, or what the philosopher Nancy Cartwright calls nomological machines,
and not just chance regularities, that ultimate destruction is our universe’s destiny. There is no escape and so this world picture is something like a
nightmare, starring the monstrous, undead cosmos, with supporting roles for the
tragic heroes trapped within who make the best of their imprisonment. To be sure, not all natural processes are deterministic or robotically mechanical: at the subatomic level, particles interact probabilistically rather than causally, and chaotic systems have fractal complexity, their patterns being irreducible to the work of the parts within them. But these are still alien, impersonal vehicles that will inevitably drive the universe to ruin.
Mathematical Mysticism
You might think that something like that engineering-centric
vision of nature is the only naturalistic one, call it what I may. But in fact
there’s an alternative that derives principally from mathematics—and
specifically from geometry. Whereas the engineer objectifies by analyzing the
world in terms of problems that call for mechanical solutions, and thus by
looking at nature, too, as an undead creator of mechanical systems, the
geometer objectifies in a more Platonic way. (Again, I’m personifying
scientific skills here, not referring to the two professional classes, namely
engineers and mathematicians.) The geometer posits nothing as messy as
processes or transient material things, but eternal relationships between ideal
structures. Mathematicians have virtually taken over postmodern physics and
thus so has geometrization, which is
this alternative form of objectification. Again, there’s the depersonalization
of nature as well as the scientist’s temporary dehumanization as he subjects his
thoughts not so much to the rigors of experiment, but to the ironclad order of
pure logic. But now aesthetic ideals of elegance, beauty (symmetry), and
simplicity come to the fore, rather than the pragmatic interest in the
construction process, because mathematics abstracts from the messy material world
in which actual work is done.
Whereas time and thus entropy rule the land of undead
nature, time is unreal in the mathematician’s picture. This demotion of time
was most drastic in Einstein’s geometrical unification of space and time in a
four-dimensional block called spacetime. Time is treated as another spatial
dimension, with all future and past moments existing simultaneously so that the
feeling of passing through time is an illusion based on our limited
perspectives. The physicist Theodor Kaluza rewrote Einstein’s equations to
include a fifth dimension, which allowed him to unify gravity and
electromagnetism, making the latter a form of hyperspatial gravity. Later
physicists followed him so that now the leading view in physics is that there
are really eleven dimensions, the four dimensions of spacetime plus other
microscopic and thus hidden dimensions of hyperspace, and particles are
explained as ripples and other patterns in multidimensional space.
All change becomes illusory in these Theories of Everything
(TOE), since the differences between material objects are due to the warping of
fixed higher dimensions of space. In Superforce,
Paul Davies says that in Kaluza’s view, there are no forces, “only warped
five-dimensional geometry, with particles meandering freely in a landscape of
structured nothingness.” In a TOE such as string theory, particles too become
locked in geometry like flies caught in amber, so the free play of particles
is like a trick of light within the geometric whole, brought about by the warp
and woof of hyperspace. Instead of causality, there’s geometric structure.
Instead of temporal flow, there’s space—or rather spaces, which are so many
varieties of “structured nothingness.” Things or objects, as such, are unreal
since what’s fundamental is what we think of as their containers, the
dimensions defined by geometric abstractions.
There are, then, two
kinds of objectification in science. There’s the instrumentalism which breaks everything down into mechanisms that
can be re-engineered precisely because they’ve all been naturally constructed
in the first place. Then there’s the mathematician’s mysticism which doesn’t analyze things in terms of parts that are assembled
into wholes by undead processes, but which unifies the apparent world with an
invisible, mathematically ideal one. The geometer’s objectification surpasses
the quasi-sociopathy of the engineering-minded scientist who sees the world (including
people, ultimately) as consisting of so many instruments and machines, since the
geometer downgrades the entire material universe. In the engineer’s picture, understanding is achieved by making, which
is to say that we understand something only if we can disassemble and
reassemble it. As Foucault put it, knowledge is power; that is, understanding
is measured by our degree of control over the subject matter. Thus, engineering
becomes paramount in science, as engineers join the undead cycles of creation and destruction in the wilderness. However, for those scientists who objectify not by instrumentalizing
but by geometrizing, mathematical contemplation is the road to understanding
reality, and instead of being adequately intuited in terms of undead or
zombielike decay, the objective world of hyperspace is more or less deified as
the Absolute, or as the so-called impersonal god of the philosophers.
To illustrate with reference to pop culture, you can see
this division in TV’s The Big Bang Theory. Sheldon Cooper is a theoretical
physicist whose job is to geometrize the world and he condescends to the
applied scientist Leonard and especially to the engineer Howard, not just
because the latter doesn’t have a Ph.D., but because they both get their hands
dirty setting up experiments and making things. Howard’s engineering is made all
the grittier by the fact that his prized invention is a waste disposal system,
albeit one used in outer space by NASA. For the more practical scientists’
part, they ridicule Sheldon not just because of his mental disorders, but
because he doesn’t live in what they consider the real world, which includes
the domain of normal social interaction. The theoretical physicist is alienated
from society, because his head is in the clouds of hyperspace, while the
engineer in the show is the most carnal of the group and the applied scientist
Leonard is the most normal, often suffering pangs of regret for his lingering
nerdiness. The natural world of undead processes is symbolized by the sexual
temptations provided by the female characters to which even Sheldon succumbs.
Thus, while the show begins by celebrating something like geometrization, it’s
gradually shifted to upholding the more pragmatic image of science. And yet
Sheldon’s childishness has always allowed the broad-based show to downplay the
religious aspect of geometrization. Sheldon reveres himself, not the higher reality
invoked by his wizardly mathematics.
Enchanted Nature and a Glimmer of Postmodern Religiosity
In the case of engineering-centered instrumentalism, science-as-mystical-contemplation
comes to an end and science is united with the businesses of creating and
selling things. Again, applied science is preeminent if reality consists of
mechanical systems flowing in a sea of fundamentally mindless but creative causal
networks. “Work!” becomes the rallying cry, as in the new atheist’s credo,
“Science wins because it works” or “Science works, bitches!” as Richard Dawkins
put it. But if reality is hyperspatial, scientists end up as Platonists and
Gnostics, and science is turned into something like theology. That is,
scientists become pantheists whose
mathematical incantations are all the works that ought to be performed, because
bodily interactions are trivial in comparison to that saving grace of ours as
lowly beings whose evolved sensibilities otherwise confine us to the
four-dimensional cave. This is why even atheists like Einstein and Hawking
can’t help but speak of God as being unwilling to play dice, of the laws of
nature as divine and as providing us a window into God’s mind, and so forth: these theoretical scientists practice
science-as-geometrization and so their objectification is virtually a
spiritualizing of nature. Objectification can be a form of enchantment
which practically (not
metaphysically) reestablishes the division between nature and supernature, in
terms of that between space (and time) and hyperspace.
Thus, the so-called war between science and religion is hardly
what it seems. The science-centered atheists are the more spiritual combatants since
they refuse to trivialize ultimate reality by personifying it as the
narrow-minded masses do when the latter practice their exoteric bastardizations
of the traditional religions. Ironically,
the so-called theists are the deeper atheists, compared to the modern
naturalists who have made a science out of mysticism and whose magic really
works in the form of artificialization (applied science). Still, the religious aspect of geometrization muddies
the waters in the culture war between science and religion, and so many
naturalists are scientismists who stand against all spirituality and
religion—even as physicists become so beholden to the mystical monks among them
that they spent billions building the Large Hadron Collider to procure some
evidence for the prevailing TOE which by many accounts is unfalsifiable and
thus effectively theological.
Mathematics has
replaced myths for modern atheistic religionists, aesthetic admiration the call
for a personal relationship with God. Instead of telling stories about the
divine order, using symbols drawn from everyday life which thus
anthropomorphize that ultimate reality—which is how religion (the worshipping
of something sacred) is practiced more as art than as science—geometrizing
scientists chart the mystical structure of nothingness using artificial symbols
drawn from math, which are so divorced from daily reality that most people
haven’t the foggiest clue what physicists are talking about. But just as myths
are meant to honour the sense that there’s a qualitatively higher order removed
from the seemingly fallen world in which we so often suffer,
geometrization provides a vision of the hyperspatial Absolute in which all
things literally move and have their being. Instead of foolishly projecting our
mammalian social instincts onto the alien Absolute, modern pantheists worship
the divine order by contemplating its aesthetic aspect, that is, its topology.
Instead of art criticism in the form of the pretentious postmodern journal for
nihilistic snobs, we have the higher art criticism of the mathematical model of
hyperspace. The elitism remains, but at least the theorists of everything
revere the ultimate art object, the structured nothingness whose ripples are
galaxies and whose twists are the fundamental forces of our universe, whereas
postmodern fine art is perpetrated mainly by charlatans.
These two kinds of scientific objectification, the
engineer’s instrumentalism and the geometer’s mysticism, seem largely at odds with
each other. Certainly, time can’t be both real (fundamental) and unreal, for
example. You might think that these approaches to science come into conflict only
when we totalize them. If we think of science as providing us with models of
phenomena, we can speak of models of spacetime and of hyperspace, and leave
aside the question of their consistency since the models may be useful for different
purposes. But then we’d be thinking of science as pragmatic, not as mystical.
The conflict, then, is between views of science, not just between views of nature. The question is whether empirical knowledge should be useful, above all else, or whether it should lead to reverence, compelling us
to acknowledge our insignificance in relation to the Absolute. Methodological naturalism begs the question in favour of the engineer’s
predilection, as does scientism since science-centered hostility to all
religion is just a tactic in a culture war: scientismists espouse an
oversimplified portrayal of science and rationality to achieve their social
goals. By contrast, the mystical scientist loses himself in contemplation, not
in Machiavellian power struggles. The question, then, is whether to identify
with the monstrous evolutions of the apparent world or to commune with a
hidden, immaterial reality through the tenuous link of abstract reasoning. Engineering,
consumerism, and dominance hierarchies or mathematical invocation, social
alienation, and cosmicist awe? Business or pantheistic worship? Needless to
say, science itself won’t answer these questions for us.
Looks like I can't science my way out of this one!
ReplyDeleteFascinating article though. Science as contemporary theology/mysticism is an interesting idea.
Your blog reaffirms my nihilism but it makes me feel good about it somehow. 10/10, would suicide to.
Thanks for reading! I'm not quite a nihilist myself, but my worldview certainly has its dark side. I'm not sure what you were saying about suicide, but I discuss that issue here, in case you're interested:
Deletehttp://rantswithintheundeadgod.blogspot.ca/2013/11/enlightenment-and-suicide.html
I was just being silly with the suicide comment.
DeleteI know you're not a nihilist; I've been reading you're blog for a while now. However, I find it difficult to derive hope or meaning from your philosophy. I can't quite come to believe in your suggestions of transcendence. Just sounds like more complex horror. I don't know, maybe I'm too pessimistic.
Well, my philosophy is a work in progress. I'd say it's not so much about hope or meaning, though, but moments of being transfixed by the sublime. Transcendence is everywhere in nature where you find evolution and complexification. And each higher level can be experienced as sublime (mind-blowing) from the lower or former perspective.
DeleteBut what if the transcendent is transcendentally horrible? Increasing complexification/emergence does not make me feel better about this world I live in, considering I don't believe in teleology. All I'm left with is the question, "What the fuck am I doing here?"
DeleteI think we have to figure that out for ourselves. The philosophy/religion I'm working out on this blog is meant to confront the worst-case scenario (an interpretation of philosophical naturalism) and to make the best of it. So in an upcoming article, I make a similar point to your question about horrible transcendence. The problem isn't nihilism, I say, but an aesthetic vision of nature's ugliness.
Delete