Karl Jaspers’ existential philosophy is similar to Sartre’s,
the main differences being their starting points and styles of writing. The
early Sartre presupposed a literary version of phenomenology as a way of doing
metaphysics, whereas Jaspers starts from science (psychology) and Kantian
philosophy. Both end up with existential conclusions about the need to
persevere despite the ultimate futility of thinking or living, but Jaspers’
psychology background gave objectivity a more prominent role in his philosophy,
which in turn lends even more readily to a cosmicist interpretation of Jaspers.
Jaspers’ Existential Take on Transcendent Knowledge
Karl Jaspers |
Descartes attempted to reestablish the foundation of
philosophy on the bedrock of self-consciousness, but instead of venturing down
the intensely personal, existentialist path—which had to wait until Kierkegaard
(although Saint Augustine’s Confessions
anticipated that development)—he compromised with dogmas, resorting to the
gambit of validating personal experience by appealing to dubious proofs of
God’s existence. David Hume brought the problem of unchained skepticism back
into the philosophical mix, showing that we can’t be sure even about something
as commonsensical as our concept of causality. This prompted Kant to concede
that although metaphysical generalizations are groundless, we can investigate
the transcendental space, as it were, of how our minds would have to be
structured to generate the human form of experience. Analogously, biologists
would later theorize that although the evolution of life is largely accidental,
there is what Daniel Dennett called the “design space” which natural selection
“discovers” and which accounts for convergence in the evolution of certain
traits across species. Physics and chemistry constrain the workable solutions of
evolutionary problems, by providing the possible niches that species can
exploit. For example, there may be a niche for highly intelligent species, in
which case if our mammalian ancestors hadn’t evolved intelligence or
self-consciousness, perhaps a reptile, bird, or mollusk might have done so and
there would have been octopus high-tech cityscapes instead of human ones. There
may, then, be meta-laws about the body-types that will tend to evolve, due to
the niches made possible by lower-level natural regularities.
Kant thus effectively redefined foundational philosophy as
an analysis of the conditions of possible experience. He argued that there are
“transcendental” conditions not of body-types but of forms of experience. For
example, the concepts of space and of time are supposedly fundamental to our
ways of sensing the world, and so while we shouldn’t be confident in generalizations
about the nature of external reality, we can be certain about what Kant called “synthetic
a priori” knowledge, meaning broad
knowledge about ourselves—but specifically about how the human mind must be
structured to generate the universal features of human experience. Kant thus
posited certain categories that determine how we generally process sensory
input, and he maintained that necessary truths that aren’t mere tautologies or
word games apply only to that proto-psychological level of analysis. We do seek
to transcend those limits, such as when we devise speculative ontologies about
God, the immortal soul or the nature of being, but these ideas mislead us if we
think we have direct access to such subject matters. Our knowledge necessarily
passes through our most general modes of understanding and thus we inevitably
project the image of human mentality, as it were, onto any subject of our
inquiry.
Now whereas Kant’s writings were highly technical and
abstract, Jaspers the psychologist-turned-philosopher saw that Kant’s
transcendentalism could be given a more human face or brought further down to
Earth, by delving into what it’s like actually to attempt to transcend the
limits of human experience. While Kant denied that it makes sense even to speak
about the noumenon (the mind-independent source of sensations, or the things in-themselves),
as opposed to things in so far as they’re processed by a type of mind, Jaspers
argued that our insatiable curiosity and our yearning to see our way past
apparent limits give us an experience of transcendence, if not rigorous
knowledge of any such thing. For example, Jaspers mapped out the steps in neo-Hegelian
progress from an empiricist/objective/scientific approach to the world, to an
existentialist/subjective/self-reflective one, to a religious/metaphysical/mystical
outlook. At each stage, we’re confronted with the limits of that approach,
which compels us to raise questions that push us towards the next stage. The empiricist
is faced with the radical doubts voiced classically by such philosophers as
Descartes, Berkeley, Hume, and Nietzsche. We’re forced to look within ourselves
for answers as to how we can trust what we think we know about the external
world. That interior line of inquiry leads us to what would later be called the
postmodern malaise, to relativism, nihilism, or to the self-destructive
solipsism of hyper-consumption—unless we jump yet again to a more encompassing
conceptual framework.
Here, however, instead of siding with Pascal or with
theology in general, which would call for religious faith to save us from the
downfall of overactive reason, Jaspers argues that we have a rational
obligation to avoid deceiving ourselves and thus to grasp the tragedy of our
existential predicament. Our search for ultimate knowledge, for knowledge of
what Jaspers called “the encompassing” or what Kant construed as the limit of
human experience, is doomed from the outset—but not exactly for Kant’s reason. Kant
said we posit God and other ultimate notions to regulate our thought processes
even though we have no hope of understanding such presumed transcendent
realities. Jaspers pointed out that
although we can’t understand them, we do experience our yearning for them as
well as the “cyphers of transcendence,” meaning hints or ambiguous messages
sent out by the world that testify to the limits of our knowledge and thus to the
existence of some transhuman reality. To make sense of the failure of the
second stage of knowledge, then, Jaspers said we turn—desperately and
futilely—to reading nature’s tea leaves, to interpreting patterns in our
experience as clues to a metaphysical puzzle we can never solve. Jaspers
eschewed organized religion precisely because dogmas prevent the personal
growth made possible only by a fearless encounter with our limits. Instead of
settling for conventional answers as though we could cognitively encompass so
easily that which by definition transcends our ordinary ways of thinking, we
can only wrestle with those limits and with the suspicion that there must
therefore be some X on the other side.
As Kant said, we can’t know the noumenon as though it were a
phenomenon, but contrary to Kant, that doesn’t mean there’s no sense in
pondering the noumenon. We shouldn’t
pretend we have systematic knowledge of that which transcends our ordinary ways
of understanding the world, as in organized religion, but we should recognize
the greater personal authenticity of those who grasp the need for metaphysical
or religious reflections. The task for Jaspers isn’t so much to fully
answer our ultimate questions, but to fulfill our potential by growing beyond
artificial limits placed on philosophical subjects of discussion. Jaspers thus
seems to view philosophy rather like the later Wittgenstein did, as a disorder
that should be cured. But whereas Wittgenstein blamed limitations of ordinary
language which bewitch us into asking meaningless questions, Jaspers blamed our
inherent restlessness which must settle for philosophy’s frustrating
incompleteness. Questions about transcendent reality may be “meaningless”
according to empiricist standards, but we’re free to live by other standards.
Moreover, if we don’t transcend the limits of positivism or scientism, we fail
to mature as persons from something like a characterological standpoint.
Jaspers thus connects existential philosophy to psychotherapy, the point being
that our mental health depends on our dealing with the challenge presented by
what Kant construed as the noumenon. We should indeed talk out the lacunas in
our experience, says Jaspers, but we should do so humbly, appreciating Kant’s
insights about the role of necessary limits in any attempt at understanding.
Metaphysics or religion thus becomes a mystical kind of talk therapy, for
Jaspers, a discourse that enables us to mature as individuals who heroically
confront the possibility of the transcendent, aware both of our cognitive limits
and of what come to look like frustrating clues about that which lies beyond
what we can know.
Transhumanism, Late-Modern Physics, and Cosmicism
Jaspers’ notion of a transcendent limit that encompasses
objective and subjective reasoning is similar to Sartre’s concept of God
as the in-itself-for-itself, the impossible union of objective and subjective
properties. Sartre insists that this concept is incoherent since the subject
requires the freedom of self-definition, whereas the object lacks precisely
that freedom. A neo-Kantian such as Jaspers would likely welcome that
incoherence as a sign of genuine transcendence— assuming the concept of God
isn’t the one belonging to some sterile, conventional religion but is the one
that makes sense of genuine religious experience. For Jaspers, the concept of
God isn’t so useful to empirical reasoning or personal decision-making, but in
challenging all human endeavours with the threat of something radically
transhuman. And a religious experience isn’t bound by any scriptural dogma,
since this experience reveals, on the contrary, that all aspects of our ways of
living are inadequate to what seems somehow to exist to have provided us with
that type of experience. This disconcerting experience of the narrowness of our
limits thus leaves us searching for a remedy for existential vertigo. Is the
world fundamentally objective? What then of human subjectivity? Where do we fit
into the objective world? And if we retreat further within subjectivity, as in
the postmodern withdrawal into endless nostalgia and irony, we lose touch with the
natural facts. The true purpose of
metaphysics or of religion is to bridge this divide, not with pseudoscientific
theories or creeds, but with informal, therapeutic discussions about the hints
we receive that perhaps everything makes sense according to some nonhuman mode
of thinking.
These existential-Kantian reflections on the nature of cognitive
limits are perfectly adapted to cosmicist purposes, that is, to grasping
the horrific implications of philosophical naturalism. The monsters, aliens, or
gods that stand out in H.P. Lovecraft’s stories, for example, are symbolic
precisely of the fear that our perspectives are limited compared to what likely
exists. The upshot is a critique of anthropocentrism—not a reckless and indeed (for us) impossible abandonment of human ways of
understanding, but a recognition that reason can grasp its limits, which leaves
us with nonrational means of coping. One such nonrational response is, of
course, terror in the face of the
possibility of transhuman modes of being. This terror is found paradigmatically
in the fear of death. Death is no mere intellectual conundrum, but an
existential burden since we know in advance that our life is fundamentally
limited. Jaspers’ point, though, is that the world’s hints that our systems are
inadequate can come at any time and from any direction. Religions themselves,
he points out, tend to hinder rather than facilitate healthy ways of thinking
about our inadequacy. Indeed, the very notion that any way of thinking could be
cognitively adequate to reality may be a wrongheaded remnant of
anthropocentrism. If thinking in general is bound to be incomplete, because
thinking is either objective or subjective, whereas reality encompasses both by
way of some third, unknowable category, this only adds to the fear that even
our ideal of perfect understanding is futile.
Note how this fear is expressed in the more recent way of
speaking of these issues, in the context of evolutionary transhumanity that’s due
to technological progress. While the Platonic and Christian assumption is that
there’s a metaphysical hierarchy of entities, the post-Hegelian or Darwinian
approach is to temporalize absolute being. We Western secularists think not so
much of a timeless God which we’re destined to be united with, but of natural
godhood lying in our future as a result of social and technological progress. We
thus mitigate the concerns raised by Jaspers and Lovecraft, by naturalizing divinity. We assume that as we
merge more and more with our technology, our species will attain godlike status—but
only in a stepwise fashion that will give us time to adjust, as opposed to our dying
and instantly finding ourselves in a transcendent realm of heaven or hell.
This is why the hypothesis of the imminent technological
singularity is so distressing, since it returns us to the Jaspersian or
cosmicist fear, to the jarring conviction that not just our paltry selves but
our whole species and history are somehow cosmically deficient. If our
techno-immortality and virtual omniscience and omnipotence will fall upon us
like a thief in the night (to paraphrase Jesus), and yet we can’t know now what
that transhuman life will be like on the other side of the societal event
horizon, we might as well be dying and whisked off to an alien reality, as in a
mind-melting psychedelic trip. Science fiction prepares us with what Jaspers
would call cyphers of transcendence, and the transhumanist subgenre breaks down
into the optimistic and pessimistic scenarios. Presumably, Jaspers would
welcome both, since he emphasizes the need for faith in a transcendent “encompassing”
and for rational doubts about any human representation of that limit. Again,
the point of transhumanism is that we’re currently in the process of
transcending our nature, which raises the specter of nonhuman intelligence that
will indeed encompass everything we thought we knew prior to that ascendance.
In short, it’s as though our religions posited caricatures of divinity only to
foreshadow the natural arrival of the real gods that will
happen as a result of human ingenuity.
Jaspers’ existential take on the limits of human ways of
thinking is corroborated also by the anti-anthropocentric advances in physics, including
quantum weirdness and the discovery of the universe’s true, mind-boggling scale
in space and time. We’ve certainly learned that our instincts and capacity for intuition
or snap judgment, which persist because of their primitive survival value, are
misleading sources of knowledge, but we trust that scientific reason already
transcends those parts of our nature. Our capacity for objectivity extracted us
from the more limited, animal mindset of creature-centric instrumentalism,
although Jaspers reverses the order of transcendence, from empirical reasoning
to subjective, inward-directed inquiry. The naturalistic point would be that
animals begin with an implicit subjective perspective, although most species
lack the capacity for meta-representations; they react to stimuli, but their
responses are largely hardwired, and the neural program has an implicit
subjective viewpoint, the imperative being to protect the self at almost all
costs (since the self carries the genes, and the genes write the program). With
the advent of objectivity come meta-representations and a higher form of
subjectivity, since we’re able to think more neutrally about the reality of things,
including ourselves; at least, we’re able to detach from stimuli, from our
reflexes and from the rest of our older neural programming, and to ponder what
things really are, independent of their evolutionary value.
Objectivity leads us not just to the problem of hyperactive
subjectivity, but to the physicist’s destabilizing picture of natural objects.
In particular, we’ve discovered that the “clockwork,” Newtonian conception of “objects,”
the neutrality and “givenness” of which conform with the underlying
instrumental imperative of early-modern science, only
approximates a deeper, stranger theory. Whereas the mechanical interpretation
of natural objects or of events renders them submissive to the implicit designer (to
God) or to agents of that designer (to us), quantum mechanics implicates the
observer in a way that seems to blur the line between object and subject.
There are no wholly given objects in quantum mechanics, since the subatomic
particles occupy superpositions and take on definite values only in relation to
an act of measurement or to other systems in the environment, which collapses
the wave function or accounts for the rarity of strange quantum effects in our daily
observations. In short, late-modern
physics presents us with cyphers of transcendence, since the universe’s physical
scale and the nature of matter are perfectly inhuman. Jaspers would add to
the horror of that indifference to human preferences something like a leap of
faith in a transhuman unity beyond
the inhumanity. At least, metaphysics
and religion are left to grapple with that prospect.
This was a really interesting essay. I have to admit, I was unfamiliar with Jaspers, I always saw him as a very transitional character in Existentialism and even German philosophy. I think I had a misconception about his religious leanings as well.
ReplyDeleteHis reaction to Kant, an existentialism flavored by it, it reminds me (just based on this essay) of Schopenhauer quite a bit. With very different conclusions about what that means for living life. I see Schopenhauer as a very cosmicist thinker in ways, but Jaspers seems like a more modern bridge. Definitely going to read more, thanks.
I don't think Jaspers is one of the more profound existentialists. His perspective is interesting because it comes from a science background. He switched from psychology to philosophy, which means he likely saw the weakness of scientism (absolutist objectification) from firsthand experience. He's isn't radical as much a compromiser--like you say, a bridge-builder; that's how I see him too. I wrote this article on him mainly because his Kantian approach works very well with cosmicism (dark, pessimistic naturalism).
DeleteSchopenhauer is certainly cosmicist as well, and he too comes from a Kantian background. Schopenhauer builds a bridge between Western and Eastern philosophy. Indeed, his philosophy reads like a neo-Kantian version of Hinduism.
Next up in this existentialist series is Kierkegaard, then Nietzsche, and then my attempt at writing a phenomenological version of my blog's philosophy.
All amazing topics. A toast to your prolific nature!
Delete