Nietzsche was atheism’s prophet. Other skeptics and atheists
before him were subversive, but perhaps none with such power and devotion to
telling unpleasant truths. David Hume dismantled the empirical case for theism
and revealed the nonrational, pragmatic basis of science, but Hume stood more for
the method of skepticism than for the conclusion of atheism. He also avoided
questions about the unsettling implications of naturalism, by appealing to a
mechanistic theory of morality, which reduced questions of what we should do,
to a crude model of how moral “sentiments” or feelings work. The Marquis de
Sade was a vigorous and scandalous proponent of atheism, and was more
subversive than Nietzsche, opting for a satirical mode of writing to illustrate
the horrific liberty that atheism entails—what Dostoevsky called the freedom in
which everything is permitted. However, de Sade’s ethical egoism and
proto-social Darwinism are fallacious and as crude as Hume’s mechanistic model
of the mind. Thus, while his writings are superficially more shocking than
Nietzsche’s, they’re also more easily dismissed. The pessimist Schopenhauer
drew out some dark consequences of naturalistic atheism, but his writings seem
to imply Eastern-inspired pantheism: he says nature has an evil or inhumane
will which we should resist by ascetically withdrawing from natural functions,
and if by “will” he meant only “energy,” he’d lose the moral force of his
pessimism since energy would be amoral.
Nietzsche’s Authentic Atheism
By contrast, Nietzsche dramatized the horror of atheism
while forcing the reader to grapple with the meaning of God’s nonexistence. He
does this most famously in a passage of Thus
Spoke Zarathustra in which Nietzsche tells a parable about an insane
atheist trying to convince fellow atheists that God’s absence has dire
consequences:
The insane man jumped into their midst and transfixed them with his glances. ‘Where is God gone?’ he called out. ‘I mean to tell you! We have killed him, you and I! We are all his murderers! But how have we done it? How were we able to drink up the sea? Who gave us the sponge to wipe away the whole horizon? What did we do when we loosened this earth from its sun? Whither does it now move? Whither do we move? Away from all suns? Do we not dash on unceasingly? Backwards, sideways, forwards, in all directions? Is there still an above and below? Do we not stray, as through infinite nothingness? Does not empty space breathe upon us? Has it not become colder? Does not night come on continually, darker and darker? Shall we not have to light lanterns in the morning? Do we not hear the noise of the grave-diggers who are burying God? Do we not smell the divine putrefaction?—for even Gods putrefy! God is dead! God remains dead! And we have killed him! How shall we console ourselves, the most murderous of all murderers? The holiest and the mightiest that the world has hitherto possessed, has bled to death under our knife—who will wipe away the blood from us? With what water could we cleanse ourselves? What lustrums, what sacred games shall we have to devise? Is not the magnitude of this deed too great for us? Shall we not ourselves have to become Gods, merely to seem worthy of it? There never was a greater event—and on account of it, all who are born after us belong to a higher history than any history hitherto!’—Here the madman was silent and looked again at his hearers; they also were silent and looked at him in surprise. At last he threw his lantern on the ground, so that it broke in pieces and was extinguished. ‘I come too early,’ he then said, ‘I am not yet at the right time. This prodigious event is still on its way, and is travelling—it has not yet reached men’s ears. Lightning and thunder need time, the light of the stars needs time, deeds need time, even after they are done, to be seen and heard. This deed is as yet further from them than the furthest star—and yet they have done it!
Never has the meaning of atheism been rendered as vividly
and as starkly as in those lines. Nietzsche wrote in an oracular and often
prophetic style, because he must have felt some kinship with the biblical
prophets who stood apart from their society to condemn its follies, since they
devoted themselves to what they regarded as the terrible truth of living within
sight of an angry and jealous God. As to those messages of the Jewish prophets and of the Christian messiah, Nietzsche
denounced them in turn for being insufficiently truthful. Judaism was slightly more
naturalistic than Christianity in treating monotheism as an excuse for the brutality
wrought by earthly kingdoms. But polytheism is the more naked rationalization
and thus the more naturalistic religious fiction. Monotheism makes divinity
transcendent, immaterial, and thus unnatural, which cleared the path for
Christianity’s otherworldly slave morality. In the real world, as opposed to the imagination of the weak-willed and
resentful masses, divinity is found only in the creativity of the most powerful
human persons. Divinity is thus mere nobility. But
because nature is amoral, it includes the capacities for treachery and
dishonour, not just for the inclination to worship human rulers and great
artists. Thus, in Christianity, “omega” and “beta” mindsets have their revenge
against the “alphas,” but by the unheroic method that’s the formers’ only
recourse. Instead of defeating natural winners at their game, demonstrating
their courage in the face of reality, Christians bewitch winners into
exchanging natural virtues with those of the natural loser, and into imagining
a fanciful utopia in which losers are explicitly rewarded while winners are
punished for eternity.
In the modern period, genuine philosophy begins, then, with
atheism and with the ability to see through the Jewish and Christian ruses, for
example. The point isn’t just that God doesn’t exist, but that mass religions
have dishonourable functions as well as some social utility in delaying the
reckoning with the dreadful truth of nature. Religions pacify populations, but a
price of civilization is the domestication of the individual and the loss of
artistic greatness, which is to say the loss of real divinity. By convincing
the human herd that everything will be alright in another realm in the
afterlife, sheepish individuals lose their incentive to create something new.
On the contrary, we fear God’s reprisals, so we obey the nonsensical morality preached
by God’s alleged earthly representatives. The result is nihilism, since by ignoring nature as a fallen place that pales
next to Heaven, the theist effectively worships nothing at all; more
specifically, she prizes a fantasy that’s meant to replace natural reality, as
in tales of the apocalyptic coming of God’s kingdom.
But theists aren’t the only ones bewitched by ignoble
fantasies. Nietzsche condemns so-called
atheists, too, for their complacency. Liberals, socialists, nationalists,
hedonists, and rationalists put their faith in unworthy idols, largely because
they haven’t understood the momentous stakes raised by God’s irrelevance in the
modern (scientifically-informed) age. The prophet Nietzsche longed for the
coming of a worthy idol, for a substitute deity that would earn our admiration.
This idol wasn’t exactly the Nazi Fuehrer, although Nazism is harder to refute
on Nietzschean grounds than many Nietzscheans would prefer to admit. Nietzsche
wasn’t himself anti-Jewish or fascistic, nor was he sadistic or a social
Darwinian who reveled in domination. But Nietzsche did stand for the glory of authentic
creativity in the face of enormous odds. The attempt to build a fascist empire
that overthrows the liberal democracies of the “Last Men” or the beta males
whipped by their female taskmasters that rule ignobly from the shadows would
seem to qualify as roughly Nietzschean in inspiration. Even the Holocaust could
be defended on Nietzschean principles, since wasn’t Judaism responsible
ultimately for the collapse of honourable polytheism and for the rise of slave
morality through the Jewish sect of Christianity? Isn’t the authentic atheist
and naturalist left with no normative guidelines besides those she creates to
celebrate the will to power that prevails in the universe? Why not, then
exterminate the Jews? In reality, the Nazis attempted to do so for lowly
reasons, because the German gentiles couldn’t admit their weakness and resorted
to scapegoating an innocent party for the downfall of Germany after the Great
War. Even were the Nazi motive to have been revenge for ancient wrongs, that
too wouldn’t have impressed Nietzsche, since heroes should be above such a
backward-looking scheme. So a Nietzschean wouldn’t admire the character of Nazis. Still, fascism (a
secular version of ancient theocracy) was new (spearheaded by Mussolini) and
Nazism was epic.
If you’re tempted to think that Nazism should obviously be
condemned on moral grounds, you haven’t grasped what’s radical in Nietzsche’s
prophetic philosophy. Morality which rejects violence for supernatural reasons
is anathema to those who are strong-willed enough to live by the truth. Animals
kill all the time, albeit almost exclusively to survive. The Nazis didn’t need
to kill Jews to survive—obviously, Jews weren’t hunted for food—but that only
testifies to our potential for divine creativity. That creativity is what
Nietzsche celebrates with his concept of the Ubermensch, of the individual who overcomes all obstacles in pursuit
of artistic ideals, and it’s why Nietzsche laments egalitarian societies that
prevent the rise of such great individuals. The problem is that perfect
equality across a wide population would require a miracle and a supernatural
designer. As Nietzsche points out, our concepts overgeneralize, strictly
speaking, by ignoring irrelevant differences between instances of a type. If
not even every chicken egg has exactly the same properties, although we regard
each as equally falling under the concept <chicken egg>, there’s much
less of a chance that every person is naturally equal to everyone else, since a
grown person is more complex than a chicken egg and so there’s more chance of
genetic and experiential variety between persons that falsifies the concept
<person>, strictly speaking. We assume we all have equal value as members
of our species, but we can be actually equal in that respect only if God
bestows on each an immaterial spirit or if a secular institution stipulates
that we have rights in virtue of our humanity. The first is a theological
fiction, the second a legal one. Realistically speaking, we’re each obviously
different, although for many practical purposes we can usefully generalize
about our type.
What is the Relativity of Truth?
Art by Alex Grey |
Take my statement that “Life is art.” Technically, I’ve said,
rather, that we can adopt an aesthetic, quasi-mystical or posthuman attitude
that makes life look only as good as art. But suppose we generalize and just
declare that life must ultimately be
merely art, the product of natural or artificial creative powers. The problem
of postmodernity reduces, then, to the interpretation of that word “be.” If we
interpret the aesthetic generalization to mean that life is art as a matter of fact, that the statement
is supposed to be true in virtue of its agreement with an objective fact, we’re
presupposing a non-aesthetic notion of truth. Again, all relativists, including
Nietzsche, are susceptible to this objection. I respond that the correspondence theory of truth makes no sense in the big,
cosmicist picture of nature, since the world toys with and tortures rather than
supports living things; our products don’t “agree with” reality, since nature is
human whereas we’re condemned to be conscious and compassionate despite the
futility of our ideals. Friends are in agreement; enemies not so much. But this
response only encourages a repetition of the objection: is cosmicism, then, supposed to be objectively
true? Am I presupposing a double standard, objectivity for cosmicism and
relativism for all other ways of thinking?
If we do presuppose objectivity at that point, this would indicate
that the scientistic myths of early modernity have wormed their way
into us. The kind of objectivity that epistemic realists have in mind is a crypto-theological
notion. In reality, science is more pragmatic than realistic, as Nietzsche
would point out. The technological applications work because scientific
theories are better than alternative ways of understanding nature, but the
success isn’t because the theories agree with reality. Scientists use
information (“natural meanings” in the philosopher Grice’s sense) to understand
the world, and that understanding is fundamentally a form of empowerment, not a
mirroring of facts; indeed, to mirror the
facts would be to become monstrous, which would be the deeper form of
self-destruction. By contrast, science is instrumental, and calling
scientific statements “factually true” honours or flatters that utility.
But what could it mean to say, as I just did, that “In
reality, science is more pragmatic than realistic”? Isn’t that just
self-contradictory? Perhaps a pragmatist should be strictly empirical, ban
herself from issuing any such generalization, and remark—like the
hyperrationalist Data from Star Trek—only on what the evidence directly supports.
So instead of speaking of the metaphysical entity of “reality,” we should speak
only of what’s present to our senses, to observables such as changes in the
instruments used in our experiments. This
positivism, however, is itself a pseudoproblem since it fails to reckon with
the nonrational side of our nature. The cosmicist generalization about
reality shouldn’t be interpreted as empirical; indeed, to interpret it that way
is itself to presuppose the philosophy or religion of scientism, and thus to violate
the conceit of hyperrationality. Instead,
cosmicism is a feeling of horror
about things in general. Aestheticism, too, is a complementary feeling of wonderment about things in
general. So when I say, “In reality, science is pragmatic,” I’m reporting on
my sense that in the ultimate picture which is more felt than demonstrated,
science, too, is a plaything of inhuman forces which surpass our understanding.
The empiricist mindset is a defensive posture meant to cope with natural
threats, as pragmatists such as Richard Rorty have pointed out. To speak of a natural object or event as a “fact”
is to belittle and humanize an indicator of inhuman reality; we seek to reduce
the world to manageable units, to tame the unknowable, and we do so to mitigate
the fear that our life is out of our control.
"However, de Sade’s ethical egoism and proto-social Darwinism are fallacious and as crude as Hume’s mechanistic model of the mind. Thus, while his writings are superficially more shocking than Nietzsche’s, they’re also more easily dismissed." How would you dismiss Hume's philosophy?
ReplyDeleteI'm opposed to the scientistic spirit of Hume's philosophy, and I think Hume's Fork is an oversimplification. Hume thought metaphysics is garbage because metaphysical statements can't be empirically verified and don't reduce to tautologies. That's pure scientism and Philistinism, which entail also the worthlessness of all forms of art.
DeleteHume's skepticism borders on a parody of empiricism. He pushed empiricism and skepticism about as far as they could go, which led us to see the problem of induction and our less than fully rational nature. But his model of the mind is crude, because it's based on a narrow view of reason. Kant showed how rationalism or transcendentalism is implicit in Hume's talk of "habits" and "customs."
"That's pure scientism and Philistinism, which entail also the worthlessness of all forms of art" Since art is totally subjective, why would it make art worthless? I don't think you've gone much further than, "I don't like it" in dispelling Hume.
ReplyDeleteIt's a reductio ad absurdum. Hume's hyperskepticism leads to the absurdities of scientism and philistinism. If you accept those implications, then start joining the Taliban and burning all artworks along with metaphysics books. Otherwise, you understand that semantic meaning isn't just logical or empirical, and that Hume's Fork is a false dichotomy. Also, you can just read Kant's transcendental elaborations to go beyond Hume's crude model of our cognitive capacities.
DeleteAccording to Ayn Rand, Kant’s objective was to save the morality of altruism, self-sacrifice, and self-abnegation. Kant’s vision of morality consists of total, abject, selflessness. Kantianism sharply opposes the pursuit of happiness to the practice of one’s duty. Kant’s morality of duty restricts the importance an individual’s experiences and thought and teaches that morality depends on adherence to a priori truths and on ignoring the real world. Rand thus saw Kantianism as a grand rationalization for Kant’s hatred of reason and reality and his view of the supremacy of the emotions.
DeletePlato is boring.....Plato is a coward in face of reality- consequently he flees into the ideal. Ultimately my mistrust of Plato extends to the very bottom of him: I find him deviated so far from all the fundamental instincts of the Hellenes, so morally infected, so much an antecedent Christian- he already has the concept ‘good’ as the supreme concept- that I should prefer to describe the entire phenomenon ‘Plato’ by the harsh term ‘higher swindle’ or, if you prefer, ‘idealism,’ than by any other.”- Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols,
ReplyDeleteAlas, the inferences Nietzsche draws from his genealogies are fallacious. Most of what Nietzsche says here is just a personal attack. Even if Plato had these personal failings, would that show that his philosophy is wrong? No, that would be the genetic fallacy.
DeleteNietzsche's saying that idealists want to escape into a fantasy world, and that may be so, but the existence of that desire doesn't make for a sufficient reason to believe that only the material world exists. For one thing, the difference between the quantum level of matter and our common experience already makes for hearty dualism. Also, Descartes could come along and say the desire is implanted in us by the higher realm, as the Gnostics also said.
Nihilism shows us the value of transcendental thought. By facing the darkness of life directly and allowing the cold wind of the abyss to lick our faces, nihilism creates acceptance of the world as it is, and then embarks on a search for meaning that is not “social meaning” because it is interpreted according to the individual based on the capacity of that individual. Nihilism is esoteric in that it rejects the idea of a truth that can be communicated to everyone, but by freeing us from the idea that whatever truths we encounter must include everyone, allows for lone explorers to delve deeper and climb higher, if they have the biological requirements for the mental ability involved.
ReplyDeleteFor this reason, nihilism is transformative. We go into it as equal members of the modern zombie automaton cult, convinced that there is objective truth and we have subjective preferences. We come out realizing that our preferences are entirely a function of our abilities and biology, and that “objective” truth is as much an idol as the Golden Calf of Moses’ time: a fiction and consensual reality created to keep a troupe of slightly smarter than average monkeys working together. Nihilism transforms us from human into beast, and from that, to something which can reach for the stars.
We can define these philosophical words how we like, but I'm not sure why you're calling that viewpoint "nihilism." As I think of it, nihilism is purely negative, the view that nothing is really meaningful. If that's the end of our philosophical exploration, we're liable to be depressed and destructive.
DeleteBut nihilism can be a creative spur if it's more precisely the idea that the objective world is amoral and value neutral, which provides us the opportunity to impose subjective meaning and purpose onto the rest of reality. Individual, inspired expressions might be more authentic than conventional ones, which puts a Romantic spin on this dynamic.
I think that's roughly what you're saying here. But this would amount to saying that nihilism is overcome or that it turns into some other, more positive philosophy. Calling both the destructive and the constructive parts "nihilistic" seems strange to me. But that could be just a matter of definitions.
This is a form of Neo-Nihilism as explained by Peter Sjöstedt-H in his excellent book, Neo-Nihilism: The Philosophy of Power.
Delete