Our life would not be worth living if we valued nothing.
Indeed, that’s a tautology, because to speak of life as worth living is, of course, to speak of life as having a (positive)
value. If we were to take the physicist’s view of the universe as sufficient
for knowledge or if we were to adopt an eastern mystical perspective on the
natural world of changing events as being wholly illusory, we would be
nihilists. In that case, we’d have to believe that values are unreal, that all
that exists is either an amoral, inhuman flow of matter and energy or some
transcendent realm in which human values are meaningless. To value something is
to assess the thing as being good or bad. If nothing is really good or bad, if
the assessments of value are, at best, self-indulgent conceptual tools we use
to accommodate ourselves to living with many strangers in civilized society,
we’re poised to lose faith in whatever we’re doing as human creatures. As the
Bible likes to say, our heart might grow as cold and heavy as a stone when,
instead of humanizing the inhuman wilderness, the opposite influx happens: the
physical object’s indifference and pointlessness infiltrate our cultures and
worldviews, bypassing our mental defenses, and we objectify ourselves and each
other. Human life takes on the aspect of an absurd game, a grotesque folly, a
blasphemous outrage.
Nietzsche declared that nihilism would be the inheritance of
the “Last Man” who would lack an authentic culture, after the death of God and
the surrender of theistic value-systems that are obsolete after the modern
discrediting of organized religions. Only if we’re saved by the grace of a
superhuman act of value-creation by some ingenious artist might we discover a
worthy faith for our time, one that’s fit for the real world. Late-modern art,
however, is arguably as dead as God. The art world is a con exploited by the
wealthy few in China, Russia, Europe, and the US to launder their ill-gotten
profits. Digitization, the proliferation of free data on the internet, and the
democratization of the paraphernalia of musicians, visual artists, and film-makers
have degraded the outputs of those media. Anyone now can be an artist, which
means art can no longer be revelatory. To the extent that art is ubiquitous and
consumed like the air we breathe, we take art for granted, and artists
themselves can be expected to die off—especially as they’re replaced by machines
and software.
The codes of civic morality, too, are arguably disgraced
along with neoliberalism (the colonization of all areas of culture by free
market principles) and social democracy, given the recent global rise of
populism. If the coda of the American century is the farce of Donald Trump’s
presidency, we might wonder whether anyone can trust that our secular
institutions have real merit. By way of illustration, consider that if the
Christian myth is that Jesus took on the sins of the world and was punished to
wipe away their stain on God’s creation, President Trump evidently stands as an
anti-Christian figure, as an unholy parody of Jesus’s sacrifice; after all, Trump
embodies practically half the sins that have ever been committed by humanity and
avoids punishment for any of them. Should we play by the rules, then, when the
justice system of the most powerful country—which drew up the plans for the
global world order—is evidently a sham? Should we bother to vote when the
leading democracy can elect a Trump or when Britain can be duped into
destroying itself with Brexit? Should we continue to participate in our
economies, when consumerism threatens to destroy the planet’s ability to
support life?
There are roughly two kinds of nihilist, the informed and the uninformed. The former deliberately sets out to believe in nothing,
due to her hyperskeptical antipathy to traditions, institutions, and other
sources of value. The latter, unknowing type of nihilist, however, is far more
common since while this type believes she has plenty of ideals and goals, these
are in fact debased; that is, even if you think you’re trying to be good and
you have a religious or philosophical story to justify your value judgments,
you’ll be effectively a nihilist if those accounts and judgments put you in
touch only with nothing in the reality outside your small-minded frames of
reference. You’ll be a nihilist except that you won’t know it; you’ll be one of
the walking dead, enthralled by some empty bits of propaganda.
However, this dire analysis is flawed, because the
“nihilist’s” austere picture of the world of objects presupposes a type of
value (besides the scientist’s epistemic standard). The “absurd game” or
“grotesque folly” of the zombified masses that flatter themselves with
high-minded self-portrayals rests on an aesthetic
reaction, albeit a negative one. The
horror implicit in the mass delusion of acting against our self-interest and
spiritual potential is hardly objective. What would be objective is a pure world
of objects in which the illusion of subjectivity or of goodness or badness is
impossible. But put the world as described by physics, together with the
delusions of religion and morality, that is, with the behaviour that takes
values to be real, and you have a mismatch. That mismatch opens the door to
aesthetic interpretation, and that interpretation won’t be arbitrary. On the
contrary, the enlightened shock in the face of mass foolishness must be
grounded in a real fall from grace, to take the Christian expression, or in a
real travesty. To appall or to astound
the philosophical elites with a showcase of existential inauthenticity, your
behaviour must be wrong in some grand fashion. That wrongness is evident from
the disgust a wise person directs towards the harm caused by gross ignorance
and arrogance.
Merlin Donald’s Three Stages of Human Cognition
Merlin Donald |
From four million to around half a million years ago, humans
had a purely mimetic mentality, meaning that the early hominids thought and
communicated nonverbally, by bodily gestures. As Donald explains,
Mimesis is an embodied, analog, gestural mode of expression that is inherently reduplicative and collective in nature. It turns the public arena of action into theater. Hence, in a sense, the primal form of distinctly human culture is theatrical, embodied, and performance-oriented. Humans are actors, and initially, in its archaic form, the public face of Mimetic culture was a theater of embodied action, manifest especially in the well-documented proliferation of refined skills among archaic hominids. It was also evident in their ability to coordinate their hunting behavior (suggesting at least some limited conventionalized gesturing) and in the emergence of ritualized patterns of cultural practice, such as coordinated seasonal migrations, shared campsites, and some division of labor. [my emphasis]
Donald points out also that “Mimetic culture still forms the
underpinning of human culture. It persists in numerous cultural variations in
expression, body language, and expressive custom (most of which people are unaware
of and cannot describe verbally), as well as in elementary craft and tool use,
pantomime, dance, athletic skill, and prosodic vocalization, including group
displays.”
Then, around two to four hundred thousand years ago, there
was a transition to what Donald calls the Mythic stage of cognition that was
centered on linguistic modeling and lent itself to story-telling.
The second major hominid cognitive transition mediated the shift from a purely mimetic form of culture to speech, storytelling, and fully developed oral-mythic culture. This revolutionary development precipitated a representational shift away from slow-moving mimetic customs, toward group storytelling, which can convey huge amounts of knowledge at speeds that are inconceivable in a mimetic context. With language, the collective knowledge base would thus have accelerated its development to the point where narrative became the dominant, or governing, cognitive mode of hominids, replacing mimetic governance with an allegorical form of thinking that I have labeled “Mythic”…Mythic culture is so named because its governing representations cohere, in any given culture, in a shared narrative tradition: an oral, public, standardized version of reality, full of mythic archetypes and allegories, can exert direct influence over the form of individual thought. The central structures of oral-mythic culture emerged as the hominid capacity for language became universal. It was a direct product of language, and it introduced both a level of culture that remains firmly at the center of human social existence, and a powerful means of recall from memory that proved faster and more precise than the imagery-driven retrieval enabled by mimetic representation. [my emphasis]
Finally, according to Donald, there was a much more recent shift
to Theoretic cognition that took advantage of literacy and related cultural
developments, producing a social class of reason-centered elites and what we
know of as philosophy and science. The cultural changes supported by the
invention of external symbols and memory came to fruition in the Axial
revolutions in the first millennium BCE, although Donald believes the effects
of those revolutions are still unfolding.
The third transition, a cultural explosion that has gradually led humanity from preliterate cultures to symbolically literate societies and theoretic governance, has been marked by a long, sporadic but nevertheless culturally cumulative history…The invention of new memory media was an event of prime importance in this transition, because it readjusted the parameters of communication and memory in the collective social-cognitive structures of society. This culminated in advanced systems of writing and the subsequent externalization of memory storage, which gradually changed the governance hierarchy so that ideas and images, and especially the historical record, were brought under centralized control.
Donald explains further how the shift from Mythic to
Theoretic cultures is from inner-focused, authority-based, closed, fixed,
stable, and highly emotive narratives, based on implicit, slow and deep
analogic logic, on the one hand, to outer-focused, analytic, evidence-based,
open-ended, unstable, much less emotive theorization based on explicit, fast
and shallow symbolic logic, on the other. However, the transitions cascaded
from one to the next, as opposed to each entirely replacing the others, so we
retain all three cognitive modes, although predominates in different periods of
history or prehistory.
The Premodern Centrality of Aesthetic Values
"All the world's a stage" |
At any rate, assuming the mimetic hominids implicitly took
the hunt to be good rather than bad, they wouldn’t have understood my
suggestion that their values were only aesthetic. Nevertheless, regardless of
the evolutionary understanding of purpose and value that informed the minds of
protohumans, the importance of certain events for them must actually have been
aesthetic, because their mentality was performative. There was nothing else to their behaviour or their mental states that
would have been susceptible to evaluation, than their living as actors, their miming
of their intentions with wild or subtle gestures to coordinate their actions.
The good of the clan was just the merit
of the performance. Suppose the hunters succeed and bring down a
wildebeest. They celebrate with the appropriate gestures, which indicate for
them that this result of their cooperation is good. The protohumans implicitly
value the dead animal as the end brought about by their risky means. But the
killing and consuming of the animal would have been the climax of the play. If
the members performed their parts well, the act would have been heroic. If the
hunt was clumsy or the hunters only got lucky in bringing down the beast, the
result would have been less admirable. The lucky hunters might feel guilty for
consuming the meat they didn’t earn, which guilt might sap their courage for
the next hunt, and so the value of that lucky first hunt plummets; that hunt
could be more a curse than a blessing. There’s
nothing intrinsically good or bad about the killing of an animal (or about
anything else), but the value of that event would have emerged from the fact that
those early hominids learned how to act as though they were engaged in theater,
by way of their establishing a mimetic, prelinguistic form of thought.
The situation is similar with respect to Mythic culture,
except that the nonverbal communication is largely eclipsed by the verbal, so
that instead of life unfolding as the scenes of a play sustained by a
protohuman talent for meaningful, nonberbal gestures, early human thought was
immersed in story-telling. Instead of
performing the meaningful events directly, taking part in the drama as actors
on the given stage (the wilderness), language-using primates could speak of the
actors who lived in the imagination and in their repeated tales. Along with
dreams, here was perhaps a root of the eventual belief in a hidden immaterial
realm of souls. The invention of fiction, of language capable of signifying not
just the expected effect of certain actions (such as the killing of the hunted
animal), but an imaginary, mythic character, an idealized hero who undertakes
instructive or epic journeys created a cultural space that was later identified
metaphysically with a supernatural realm.
In any case, while early humans might have conceived of
their values in more elaborate, religious or moral terms, again in so far as
their mentality was mythic, in Donald’s sense of being governed by the telling
of stories, those values must have been fundamentally aesthetic. Like bodily performances of roles in an
effective theater, stories are literally works of art. Therefore, any
aspect of human life that inherits its meaning and value from a myth or legend
or from an oral culture is to that extent an aesthetic phenomenon. Suppose, for
example, the early humans spoke of the importance of hunting, by telling tall
tales to instruct the young members of the tribe. Such tales would likely have
passed on folk knowledge about how best to hunt as a team, about why cockiness
should be avoided and the prey respected. Just as the value of the results of
the hunt used to depend on the skill with which the performance was carried
out, now it depended on the artistic merit of the story. Was the story
sufficiently compelling, dramatically speaking, to persuade the tribe to obey the
lesson?
Art and Objectivity
With the shift to Theoretic culture in the Axial and later
Scientific Revolutions, we seem at first glance to leave behind the centrality
of aesthetic values and perhaps even to enter a world in which values have no
place at all, since Theoretic culture is concerned more with rational
acceptance of factual truth. But this loss of value is only superficial, since
the centrality of aesthetic values reemerges in a surprising way. With its
external memory capacity and elaborate hierarchies of knowledge of how nature
actually works, Theoretic culture is famous for disenchanting its subject
matter, for alienating the theorists from the world precisely to the extent
that they’ve attained an abstract overview of objective processes.
Thus, a key difference between the first two mentalities and
the Theoretic is that the former permitted and indeed counted on the suspension of disbelief in the
service of the aesthetic values that made early human life worth living,
whereas reason-centered culture hinders that suspension. By learning how natural processes work, by objectifying and studying
nature and recording the literal descriptions and explanations for posterity,
Theoretic culture drains natural phenomena of magical, religious, moral, and
aesthetic qualities. These qualities become illusory, at best, in the light
of rational understanding. A rational theorist can entertain a religious myth
about the gods who control the weather, but she’s prevented from believing in
the story, by her scientific understanding of the relevant impersonal causes
and effects. We still enjoy stories as entertainments, and so our societies
have an aesthetic domain, but we don’t believe that human life or any other
part of nature is dramatically meaningful in
reality as opposed to fiction. In place of the drama of life on earth with our
fellow animals, or the drama disclosed in treasured stories, we have abstract,
impersonal theories to match the indifference of objective causality and of a
disenchanted universe.
But this
objectification of nature ironically prepares the way for the reemergence of
aesthetic value, since objective knowledge produces an avalanche of
technologies and thus the deep artificiality of our Theoretic civilizations.
There, then, is the modern centrality of aesthetic value, in the creation of an
artificial world that displaces the wilderness. The protohuman hominids became
actors performing a play; later, the early humans spun myths that occupied
their imaginations and inspired their actions; and the Theoretic cultures
engage in something like the art of sculpture, in creating a host of machines
and other artifacts as the fruits of our bounty of objective knowledge.
To be sure, not all artifacts are just sculptures, since we
think of technologies as having instrumental
purposes. We program computers with software, for example, literally
encoding the intended purpose into the machine. Still, we face the fact that
instrumental purposes are nowhere to be found in the things themselves. Mass
producers of goods such as books, soft drinks, and automobiles tell us how the
products are best used, perhaps even providing an instruction manual that lays
out exactly how the products are best operated. But none of that
instrumentality amounts to real value. Those hypothetical imperatives, as Kant
showed, amount to descriptions and are thus consistent with the theoretic,
objective mindset. If you drive a car
in the intended manner, you should
enjoy such and such effects, which amounts to saying only that a certain causal
relation is in effect. Any deeper meaning in the instrumental use of artifacts
is indeed illusory, since such a prescription translates into a description.
Only when we treat all artifacts as akin to paintings, sculptures, music,
films, or other physical works of art do they take on value as expressions of
artistry. In so far as instrumental
artifacts have irreducible value, that value must be aesthetic to be consistent
with Theoretic objectivity.
Again, we don’t ordinarily think of cars or soft drinks as
works of art, since we’re more interested in their utility, in the
instrumental, causal relations that make up our civilized form of life. Those
interests amount to effective mass nihilism, however, otherwise known in the
West as cultural materialism or consumerism. If you asked the average person to
explain the value she places on her smartphone, she’d say the device is good
because it’s useful; specifically, the device makes her happy by connecting her
with the rest of society in the prevailing fashion, by making her feel safe, by
entertaining her, and so on. To speak of such instrumental values, though, is
to speak indirectly of objective, impersonal facts, such as those that arise
from the causal relations exploited in the invention of the smartphone.
Re-enchanting the
world and escaping effective nihilism would require appreciating the artistic
role of everything we create. Art historians say art has various purposes,
including the communication of ideas, the creation of a sense of beauty, the
exploration of perception, or the engineering of pleasure or other strong
emotions. An aesthetic interpretation of artificiality in general and of the
high-tech world of Theoretic cultures, in particular, would have to uncover
such roles of those items we regard as “tools,” “goods,” or “private properties,”
in our profane, effectively-nihilistic mindset. This interpretation would have
to account for the hiddenness or occult aspect of this artistic purpose. For
example, the aesthetic purpose and merit of the high-tech world might be widely
recognized only at the end of some incubation period, such as at the point when
we’ve reached the so-called technological singularity which some futurists
speculate will generate either heaven or hell on earth in the form of a
posthuman species. Either way, the aesthetic value should be continuous with
that of premodern life in Mimetic and Mythic cultures. As I stress
elsewhere, the irony of objective knowledge is that it
produces the very personalized world of intelligently-designed and controlled
artifacts that the ancients only imagined to exist with their animistic
projections onto nature.
No comments:
Post a Comment