In his debate on whether God is necessary for morality,
Christian philosopher William Lane Craig argues that for the naturalistic atheist,
human life must ultimately be insignificant, because in the end the natural
universe would destroy itself and all living things would die. Thus, morality must
be illusory and so that atheist should be prudent rather than altruistic. By
contrast, theism implies that human life and morality are fundamental to the
real world, since they would depend on God, and the spirits of moral
individuals would be united with God for eternity. Craig’s opponent, Yale
philosopher Shelly Kagan, retorts that the question of whether our life is
cosmically or ultimately important is irrelevant. Our values and duties can be
objectively meaningful, he says, even if we’re not important in the grand
scheme of things. Kagan asks Craig why we should think that objective meaning
must be on a cosmic scale if it’s to amount to anything at all. Even if in the
end everything winds up being the same, say in the heat death of the universe,
both the atoms that produced Hitler and Gandhi, what we do on our way to that
final destination can have real, if limited importance—and Kagan adds that this
importance needn’t be merely subjective or illusory. The importance of our
choices and experiences can be real even if that importance isn’t cosmic or
everlasting; moreover, the reasons to be moral can be objective even if those
reasons won’t affect the outcome of the entire universe. Kagan says that if you
save a human life, the moral significance of that action isn’t diminished one
iota by the fact that our sun will eventually explode and destroy our planet. (See
the beginning of Kagan’s interrogation of Craig, starting at around 53:20 in
the YouTube video of their debate).
As usual, Craig tries to reduce naturalistic atheism to its
most extreme form. He thinks atheism implies nihilism or at least subversive
existentialism, but because Craig’s only using the dark atheistic argument about
our status in the cosmic scale as a means to his Christian end, he doesn’t seem
to understand this argument and so he doesn’t deal effectively with Kagan’s
objection. At one point, Craig says in exasperation that he just doesn’t
understand why Kagan can’t see that all our deeds become trivial in light of
the cosmic doom that awaits us all (see 1 hour and 15 min. into the debate).
Now, I actually agree with Craig and disagree with Kagan regarding the question
of whether we should be concerned about our cosmic insignificance. We should be
so concerned. I also disagree with Craig, though, because I think atheistic
morality becomes worthy precisely when that morality deals well with our cosmic
insignificance.
The Relevance of Our Cosmic Irrelevance
Here’s how Craig should have explained to Kagan the relevance of our cosmic doom. For the naturalistic atheist, there’s a conflict between natural and social processes. Metaphysically, she thinks all processes are natural, of course, but in our daily lives we prefer to live in society, not in the wilderness. Scientists want to understand how nature works so that we can prevent nature from intruding on society. We want to predict or control the weather, to tame or eliminate wild animals, to combat diseases, and so on. We prefer our artificial, social worlds made up of human relationships and technological luxuries, because we matter in those human-made bubbles. In fact, in society we’re of central importance; everything in society points to us, because society is filled with artifacts whose functions are designed by people to serve people. Perhaps we’ve always been vainly anthropocentric for as long as we’ve been self-aware, and we satisfy our infantile urge to be at the center of the universe, by building our artificial worlds within the natural world.
But we tend not to lose ourselves completely in our fictions.
Once we see there’s this conflict between society and nature, we can ask
ourselves what the wild part of the world is up to. And what naturalists have
learned is that what seems wild to us is just a byproduct of nature’s
impersonality. Nature is mindless and set on its own course and all of human
history is a sideshow by comparison. Nature is busy, to be sure, creating and
destroying itself, proceeding inexorably to some final equilibrium in which
life probably has no role at all.
There are three main reasons why this conflict between the
human-centered world and the rest of the universe should trouble us. First, the fact that nature is in the process of
doing its own thing makes us dupes in that we unwittingly serve nature’s
inhumane agenda. It’s as if we’ve all been kidnapped by superpowerful
aliens who let us appear to live out our lives even though our society is just
a laboratory for them to study us to fulfill their nonhuman purpose. We may
find meaning in our life and take pleasure in this or that event, but the fact
that there are two worlds, one of which trumps the other, means that the
smaller world becomes absurd and ridiculous by comparison. How so? Because when
we think objectively, we detach from our personal preferences, think outside
the box of social conventions, and look at how the human-centered world relates
to nature as a whole. From that wider perspective, the rules of our human games
appear self-contained, fragile, and misleading. All games appear ridiculous to
the spectator who doesn’t identify with the players.
Think how an alien would interpret golf or baseball or indeed
how we would interpret an alien’s queer pastimes. As long as we’d remain
detached from the alien culture, we’d look down on the aliens, just as Western
anthropologists actually looked down on newly-discovered tribal societies. It
wasn’t just that those societies were less powerful than the Europeans.
Precisely because the anthropologists were relatively objective about those
societies, the foreigners’ preoccupations were of no concern to the scientists
and so their rituals, celebrations, and so on were perceived as meaningless.
But because those foreign cultures were nevertheless elaborate and apparently
fruitless, they also seemed embarrassingly wrongheaded. This happened to be
because those cultures were invariably theistic and thus otherworldly. So when
a person was sacrificed to the blood god, that cultural practice was
objectively anticlimactic, since there was no such god and thus no real point
to the sacrifice, however ironically elaborate the rituals may have been. Mind
you, objectivity undermines all culture in a similar way, because objectivity puts
us in touch with the world of objects in which meaning and value are
irrelevant, which is why the notion of “objective importance” is an oxymoron.
Objectively, which is to say, from nature’s viewpoint, as it were, nothing is
important because nature isn’t alive and thus natural forces and elements can
deem nothing as worthwhile. Natural processes flow as undead evolutions and complexifications. And when
we put ourselves in an objective frame of mind, we detach from the side of ourselves that assigns things meaning and worth; we ignore our desires and our
tastes and consider the bare facts, which the naturalistic atheist thinks
define fundamental reality. For the naturalist, mindless, material objects
are fundamental, not social obligations or cultural importance.
Second, then, the
more we think objectively, the more detached we become from our parochial
concerns, this being the opposite of the “going native” process. When the
anthropologist goes native, she switches her allegiance from one culture to
another, so that whereas she might have once found a foreign culture to be bizarre,
she comes to feel more comfortable with that other lifestyle and outlook. The
existentialist points to an inverse process of going nowhere. The curse of reason is that we all have
the capacity to go nowhere, to think in a relatively detached and neutral way, even
if we rush back to our more pleasant, anthropocentric perspective. When we
think objectively of the facts, we become as cold and calculating as any
natural mechanism. We strip off our humanity and observe the plain facts. We
recognize that the real world isn’t beautiful, contrary to the mathematician’s
or physicist’s frivolous evaluations, nor is that world humane or friendly.
Objects merely are as they are and instead of interacting at a psychological or
social level, they causally affect each other and are forced to change.
Granted, emergent levels of nature may be as real as the
lower levels, but there’s still the danger that the more we consider the lower ones,
the more we’ll dehumanize ourselves. Kagan brushes this worry off by saying
this dehumanization would be just an empirical aberration, just as some theists
will miss the point of the theistic ideal, by believing in God just so they can
go to heaven. But Kagan is mistaken; the curse of reason is more like a destiny
than an anomaly. We all have the potential for abstract thought, and language,
empathy, and other factors drive us to step outside of our social cocoons now
and again, to switch perspectives and finally to imagine how we must seem from
the objective person’s view from nowhere. This was the famous plight of
Sherlock Holmes: his superhuman ability to understand the cold, hard facts
alienated him from society; he became infected by nature’s impersonality, as it
were, because he identified with nature’s antisocial view from nowhere and it
was just reason that drove him there.
Thirdly, although the end of the universe doesn’t directly
affect us here and now, that horrible endgame does indirectly affect us, because the end of nature is part of the long
natural process which is going on right now under our feet and which reaches
into our social bubbles in countless ways, popping them before we rush to
reinflate them. That’s just to speak of the conflict again between society and
the wilderness. The wild forces of
nature and every natural turn of events are harbingers of life’s cosmic
insignificance, because they’re part of the natural world which is ultimately
opposed to life. Granted, nature can’t be entirely so opposed, since life
evolved within the natural domain. The sun is a natural object and it makes
life possible. The cosmos creates life in some of its pockets here and there, but
because nature is generally undead rather than living or inert, organisms
inevitably come into conflict with their maker. Once created, living things become
preoccupied with their survival, greedily demanding more and more security,
evolving more and more self-defense mechanisms, so that every sign of nature’s
underlying indifference to the life it created makes for a rude awakening. Whether
it’s the finitude of our bodies, the fragility of our ecosystems, the frugality
of the environment, or the brutality of the life cycle, we organisms prefer to
take up our perspectives, to think subjectively as fish, lizards, birds, or
mammals, and to cope as best we can with the fact that the world’s mindlessness
impinges on us in countless ways, often, if not always, to our detriment.
Sometimes we’re lucky, as nature’s indifference expresses itself in some
accidental benefit to a critter, but in the end, good luck, like life in
general, is temporary. The universe is ultimately opposed to life, not just
because life won’t be present in the universe’s endgame, but because that final
lifelessness indicates the underlying meaninglessness of everything in the
universe, from the objective view from nowhere.
Is Atheistic Morality a Delusion?
Let’s look closer at some relevant points from the
Craig-Kagan debate. Craig says that for an atheist, when a prison guard
tortures a prisoner, that event is of no ultimate or objective importance,
however much the torture may matter subjectively to the victim. It’s important
to analyze the key terms here. Again, the issue of objective importance is a red herring. “Objective” means reality-
or fact-based, as opposed to expressing an idiosyncrasy. For the naturalist, the
real world beyond the inner and social worlds of subjects is material, and of
course material things as such are neither important nor unimportant, because
matter is understood scientifically, not morally or theologically, and
scientific theories don’t posit values or meanings. Moreover, so-called
objective meaning for the monotheist derives from God who would be a subject
rather than an object.
So the deeper issue is whether moral values are of ultimate importance. Although Kagan
answers the point about the torturer by saying that that suffering matters to the
victims and to his or her family, he’s explicit that he means the immorality in
question isn’t merely subjective or illusory even though human morality may be irrelevant
to the cosmos as a whole. That is, Kagan says the question of our ultimate
importance should itself be unimportant to us. I agree that that question
shouldn’t matter to us if we want to be happy, because in that case we should
stop asking questions and should focus on nonphilosophical issues of daily
living. But reason sets that question before those who are cursed to think too
much. Again, we can set aside the strawman worry that the lifelessness at the
end of the universe somehow directly
makes our present lives unimportant. No, the existential concern is that the
universe’s end state indicates certain indifference on the part of all natural
processes which lead up to that end state by way of their causal connections
and inherent natures.
But let’s confront Kagan’s question which befuddled Craig: why
must our real importance as sentient creatures be either ultimate or nothing at
all? In other words, why can’t real importance, meaning, or value come in
degrees? The objection here is that Craig’s argument against nontheistic
morality rests on a false dichotomy between (A) the cosmic importance of
morality, which is precluded by naturalistic atheism, and (B) sheer nihilism
given the horror of appreciating the lack of any such ultimate meaning. Now, I
agree with Kagan that Craig’s argument does assume a false dichotomy. A
naturalistic atheist who appreciates our existential predicament and who feels
the horror in question needn’t think all values are illusory, although she will
likely defend the subjectivity of values. Nietzsche, for example, was one such
atheist who was an existentialist but not a nihilist. I’m another such atheist.
Many new atheists likewise aren’t nihilists, although they tend not to dwell on
the existential implications of their metaphysical naturalism.
Can real worth come in degrees, though? For example, can the
immorality of the torture of an innocent person be real if that event is
morally neutral along with everything else, from the rational view from
nowhere? We should grant, with Craig, the reality of subjective meaning and value.
Clearly, the torture would matter to certain individuals, but although their
feelings would be real, the subjective badness of the torture would be an
expression of those feelings. As for the fact of the torture itself, as an
objective part of the natural universe, again the question is rather loaded
against the moralist since the notion of a moral
fact is another oxymoron. Values require subjects. Still, some aspects of
values may be objective. For example, the undeadness of nature carries the
potential to horrify rational creatures, just as the universe’s lifeless
destiny is potentially tragic, meaning that rational creatures would interpret
that pattern more likely as tragic than as comedic. In any case, we need to
distinguish between the reality that some people condemn the torture and the
reality of the torture’s badness. What is it about the real world that would
make the torture wrong, given naturalistic atheism? In the debate, Kagan says
it’s the social contract, which obliges all rational beings who live together to
agree to certain rules that make society feasible. The problem with social
contract theory, though, is that perfectly rational beings would be forced to consider
the natural differences between people, as opposed to abstracting from those
differences and treating everyone as equal. So more powerful people would have
less reason to take the contract seriously than would weaker folks who would more
likely rely on its laws.
The Ethics of Existential Cosmicism
My view is that moral
values are real in so far as they reckon with our existential predicament;
otherwise, they’re delusory. Torturing an innocent person would be bad in
so far as that victim can be pitied for its having been her turn to pay for the
universe’s overall indifference to life. In other words, with the existential
perspective in mind, and thus with an acknowledgement of the cosmic absurdity
which Kagan wrongly thinks is irrelevant to morality, we can understand the reality
of moral values. Torture is wrong not just because we happen to oppose it, but
because the supreme philosophy/religion, of which my existential cosmicism is
just an inkling, would likely posit that while nature, the undead god, is
mindless, it’s also inherently monstrous. Everything
in nature is already horrible unless it’s transmuted by ascetic rebellion or
detachment which necessarily takes into account our existential plight. That
plight is that we have the potential to be heroic if we step out of our comfort
zone, recognize the horrors of what and of where we are, and manage to creatively
overcome them. Scientifically, there’s no such horror, nor any beauty or
ugliness in nature, but science is methodologically naturalistic, and philosophical
naturalism has existential implications. Were there no life in the world, nature
would still be a monstrous god, self-evolving and complexifying like a zombie
that shouldn’t be able to move as if it were alive, but which does just that. To
be sure, there would be no one to feel the horror in response to that
undeadness, but the potential for that horror would remain.
This is the objective basis of existential values. These
values (e.g. courage, pity, originality, detachment/objectivity, ironic
reversal) are creative responses to the confrontation with natural reality, and
so the values do justice to the underlying facts as well as living up to the
aesthetic ideal of avoiding conformity (cliché). You might be wondering why we should
care about the aesthetic ideal. Well, creativity in the service of an ascetic
rebellion against nature’s indifference to us has the benefit of ironically
mirroring nature’s undead creativity; moreover, there’s a fact of the matter as
to whether some thought or action is creative. In theory, creativity could even
be quantified, by contrasting something’s novelty with an average. But are
creativity and existential rebellion really
valuable or just subjectively so? The
former, since these values don’t merely express our feelings; rather, they’re
part of a posthuman process that begins
with the shedding of delusions and with the confrontation with natural horrors,
and that ends by producing godlike creativity in us. The rightness of
existential/aesthetic values is real in that it’s fact-based; nature is
objectively horrible in its monstrous mimicry of a living creator, and when we
face up to that fact and deal heroically with it, by reversing nature’s monstrous
course as far as we can, we paint our masterpiece over the ugliness of nature’s
decay.
But your "indifference to life" thesis is not a moral state at all. It just IS.
ReplyDeleteYou CHOOSE to feel HORROR about this nature of reality, but that choice and that emotion has no objective reality...it is your choice to respond to ultimate reality in this way.
Other choices might include equanimity, acceptance, passivity. These choices are no less moral and no less accepting of reality.
Your choice to feel horror is based on an underlying decision that there SHOULD be purpose, that the universe SHOULD be "nice" and have a "positive" purpose. is this not somewhat presumptuous in an almost hubristic way?
When you say that the universe's indifference to us just IS, I agree but that's part of nature's tendency to horrify us. Likewise, in the fiction, zombies just ARE and that's what's so horrible about them. How do they move with no soul? I agree that it's possible to be a naturalist but not to feel that horror. Whether we're horrified by the world depends in part on our character. But the more we think about the effects of nature's impersonality, such as the suffering caused by accidents, diseases, and so on, the more we'll have in common with existentialists.
DeleteThere are two main ways of avoiding the horror which is then a natural reaction as opposed to what you call a choice: there are the delusions of mass culture and there's the Eastern religious tradition of detachment. When you speak of equanimity and so forth, I think you're talking about the latter rather than the former, and indeed detachment and depersonalization seem to me more respectable than sticking your head in the sand. The reason we'd have to depersonalize ourselves is to avoid feeling empathy and pity for those who suffer all around us. I know Buddhists are supposed to be compassionate, but I think Buddhism is inconsistent on this point.
I don’t know if this makes any difference to your thesis, but modern cosmology and physics point to a vastly more capacious realm of reality than our poor “Hubble Volume,” which is the observable universe that presents itself to us because of the limit on the speed of light.
ReplyDeleteSky map surveys in the last decade have settled, to a high degree of probability, the topology of the universe. It’s not finite but unbounded, but spatially infinite. As Bradley Monton pointed out in a short but wonderful paper, this means we should expect that there are an infinite number of inhabited planets scattered throughout the infinite universe, no matter how rare life is; even more, there are an infinite number of planets inhabited by intelligent beings similar to us, and even an infinite number of duplicates or near duplicates of earth with each and every one of us duplicated infinitely.
Moreover, when we speak of the path from Big Bang to heat death, we’re talking about our cosmos only; but inflationary cosmology suggests that our universe pinched off from a larger meta-universe that has always existed and always will exist, and that these “bubbles” are always happening, constantly bringing new universes with the prospect for life into existence. Nature has no beginning or end under these ideas, and indeed given these facts it seems we ought to look forward to some reasonable facsimile of Nietzsche’s Eternal Recurrence, which he meant as a metaphor but may be real.
I don’t know, maybe these facts make things even more horrible!
Finally, your advice on the most logical or efficacious philosophical stance reminds me of Schopenhauer’s advice that we should treat all with compassion because they are fellow suffering travelers on a meaningless journey.
Amen to the Schopenhauer reference! He's speaking here for the non-egoistic, Eastern view of morality.
DeleteI talk about the multiverse in my myth of the undead god. God's being would be infinite, so the translation process would likewise be infinite (the quantum fluctuations). Funneling God into a form that could be annihilated would be timeless, but from the perspective of creatures inhabiting part of God's sprawling undead body (a universe in the multiverse), God is effectively dead since he's eternally killing himself by creating worlds, as opposed to intervening and making things better, and those worlds each tend to fate out in some horrible way for living things. As in certain transhuman science fiction stories, species may find eternal homes somewhere, but the vast majority of universes end badly for life, because their purpose isn't to put divine benevolence into practice; instead, it's to transduce a personal form of transcendent creativity into domains of natural creations so those iterations can be eliminated.
I think you're asking, though, whether the eternal recurrence idea is consistent with the idea of crossing a creation off the list, since that very creation would be repeated infinitely many times. But it sounds redundant to talk about an infinite universe on top of a multiverse. When you say there are duplicates of us in our universe, is that in addition to the near-duplicates in the multiverse, made by quantum fluctuations? I think you must be making a leap here somewhere, because as far as I know, how we should answer Fermi's Paradox is still an open matter.
Have you read Lee Smolin's book Time Reborn? There may be something fishy about modern cosmology. He brings in Leibniz's Identity of Indiscernibles Principle, which would count against eternal recurrence. The undead god myth seems more consistent with infinite universes if each of them is slightly different. If two are identical in every respect, it's hard to see an elimination process at work. I think we could distinguish those intrinsically identical universes by looking at their different relations to other universes.
I haven't read Smolin's book yet. The duplicate earth idea is a consequence of the spatial infinity of space, and is Level 1 of the physicist Max Tegmark's Four-Level Multiverse. The basic idea is that if the universe is spatially infinite, every possible configuration of matter and energy must necessarily be duplicated an infinite number of times. Tegmark estimated that to visit our nearest duplicate earth neighbor would require that we traverse a distance of space equivalent to the diameter of the observable universe (the so-called Hubble Volume) multiplied by four. HIs four-level multiverse article is online. For Tegmark, the four-level multiverse is: spatially infinite universe instantiates every possible outcome infinitely many times; the quantum multiverse; the inflationary multiverse and the mathematical Platonist multiverse, in which every mathematical structure is isomorphic with a physical universe. Also see Bradley Monton's work on design inferences in an infinite universe.
ReplyDeleteI've had a look at his website and some related articles. Tegmark seems to rely on probability theory to explain why an infinite space would have to be populated by everything that's possible, including duplicates of everything. As he says in his Scientific American article, "In infinite space, even the most
Deleteunlikely events must take place somewhere."
But Leibniz's Law says such duplicates are impossible. Either way, this is at best popular science, which is to say pretty much philosophy rather than science. There's no empirical evidence for this sort of multiverse. There's the math and the interpretations of its implications, including the analysis of the relevant concepts, which is a philosophical task.
Anyway, it's certainly interesting to think about parallel worlds. I like Bostrom's simulation arguments.
Have you heard of Mitchell Heisman?
ReplyDeletehttp://www.suicidenote.info/
I'd heard of him, but I hadn't before seen his 2000 page philosophical suicide note published in such a convenient form. Thanks very much for the link. I've been meaning to write something on nihilism. Specifically, I've been reading some Emile Cioran, but his writing style is a little too postmodern (needlessly cryptic) for me. I think I'll focus on Heisman. He was certainly full of ideas and some of them seem similar to mine. Of course, he appreciated all too much the curse of reason:
Delete"My hypothesis, based on my own life experience, is that objectivity taken to its extreme selects against the subjectivity of the observer, and in its most advanced form,
is rational self-destruction."
You're welcome, I only recently found out about him. His Wiki page was deleted, no surprise really. He seemed genuinely interested in pushing the boundaries of nihilism. I'm going to do my best, to make sure all of the sites I visit become aware of him. I love Cioran, but agree about his writing style.
DeleteCiron wrote, "Is it possible that existence is our exile and nothingness our home?"
ReplyDeleteOne must also mention the Norwegian philosopher Peter Wessel Zapffe, who until fairly recently had never been translated into English. His darkly lyrical essay The Last Messiah advocates human self-extinction, and is echoed today by anti-natalists. Not sure how to imbed active links here, but you can cut and paste the link to The Last Messiah: http://www.scribd.com/doc/55546861/The-Zapffe-Essay-the-Last-Messiah