Neuroscientist Karl Friston |
In a co-written paper, called The Markov blankets of life:autonomy, active inference and the free energy principle, Friston
incorporates the machine learning concept of a Markov blanket. This “blanket”
is that which “defines the boundaries of a system in a statistical sense,” the
authors write. The states that make up the blanket can be “partitioned into
active and sensory states,” meaning the states that occur spontaneously inside
the organism, such as its interpretations or its voluntary bodily movements,
and those states impressed upon the organism from the outer world, such as its
sensations. Thus, the trick in life is to infer or control the unknown causes
of the sensory states, by employing the active states. When this is done
poorly, the organism is bound to be surprised by the world which makes for wear
and tear, including ill-health and eventually death. We can control
circumstances only for so long, of course, before the universe of unknowns nullifies
our feeble schemes for holding them back or transforming them.
Here, though, is how Friston and his cowriters lay out some
of the ideas:
Active inference, in its simplest formulation, describes the tendency of random dynamical systems to minimize (on average) their free energy, where free energy is an upper bound on (negative) marginal likelihood or evidence (i.e. the probability of finding the system in a particular state, given the system in question). This implies that the kind of self-organization of Markov blankets we consider results in processes that work entirely to optimize evidence, namely self-evidencing dynamics underlying the autonomous organization of life, as we know it. In Bayesian statistics, the evidence is known as ‘model’ evidence, where we can associate the internal states with a model of the external states.
any system that minimizes entropy by acting to minimize uncertainty about the hidden causes of its sensations must have a model of the kind of regularities it expects to encounter in its environment. This means that, over (phylogenetic and ontogenetic) time, an organism will become a model of its environment…In other words, it suggests that regularities in the environment of an organism become embodied in the organism—if the organism or species persists. Under the free energy principle, this implies that organisms are close to optimal models of their local surroundings, i.e. their niche. Organisms become close to optimal models by minimizing variational free energy, which bounds the evidence for each phenotype or individual model [25]. This does not imply that an agent must (somehow) construct an internal model (i.e. representation) of its outer environment. It simply means that an agent becomes a statistical model of its niche in the sense of coming to embody statistical regularities of its world in its physical and functional composition.
Applying these biological concepts to the evolution of culture and of people would amount to a Theory of Everything—for Normies. The goal
in human life, too, would be to map and to control the unknown, and the complete
elimination of surprise would be dystopian. Friston’s theory arises from the
pretense of hyperrationality and so evinces the lunacy that’s
commonly mistaken for neutral sanity.
Subversive Meta-Cognition
To see how that’s all so, consider the basis for Friston’s
talk of optimality. If active inference doesn’t require a representational
model of the environment, which is to say a higher-order mind with meaningful
internal states, but only internal regularities which statistically are
correlated with those transpiring beyond the organism’s boundaries, that
mapping is as inherently meaningless as any other real pattern found throughout
the lifeless cosmos. Whether the matching of internal and external regularities
persists or succumbs to disorder isn’t objectively optimal or tragic. The mere
“physical or functional” embodiment of external patterns, as in the evolution
of a phenotype with traits adapted to exploit a niche, is as value-neutral as
anything else that apparently happens for no reason in nature.
There are, then, only two sources of value that would
warrant the ascription of optimality to the match between the regularities.
First, of course, the organism can
make that determination, assuming some such match is instrumental to the
organism’s survival, in which case the optimality is subjective because it
depends on the creature’s preference. Second, a theorist such as Friston can posit the optimality according to
epistemic criteria for success in explaining phenomena. Even if many creatures
have no explicit self-understanding or preferences or any other higher-order
thoughts, the theorist who explains their behaviour can deem certain patterns relevant
to certain scientific goals, in which case the source of that value-judgment is
the appeal of useful theories.
Moreover, even if the probability involved in active
inference or Bayesian reasoning is objective, in the case of people, at least,
the data must still be understood and interpreted using concepts that always simplify the unobserved causes of sensory states. If the organism does
employ representational models, the concepts indeed select relevant or interesting parts of the environment by way of
staving off confusion, boredom, or insanity when faced with the fear that the
totality of the unobserved cause, that is, the whole of natural reality is
incomprehensible and overwhelming. If instead the organism only reacts
instinctively to the environment, without thinking about its responses, the
genes are nevertheless crucial to nature’s selection of the heuristics and the
responses, which makes the organism’s species-centricity even more arbitrary
since the genes and the environment do so mindlessly.
What this means is
that Friston leaves out the possibility of horrific meta-cognition, of mystical
contemplation of the futility and absurdity of normal, instrumental cognition.
Suppose, for example, a philosopher ponders the business of being alive in
Friston’s sense, and realizes that “surprise” would be a euphemism for “terror”
or “awe.” To be surprised by the environment that doesn’t play along with our
expectations isn’t just to be disappointed or annoyed, since the disparity
entails the gamut of existentialist wisdom about how the world beyond the
confines of our mind is alien in its indifference to our struggles. The organic
enterprise of converting that absurdity to a manageable form, namely to one
that reflects our self-familiarity may be commonplace, but that hardly implies
optimality. This is because the normies have to contend with a rival type of
cognition, with the type that sees through highfalutin displays of conservatism. You
can presume that putting our spin on the environment and going as far as to
replace the wilderness with an artificial refuge is optimal or proper, given
established standards, but even this relativist judgment is easily defeated, as
the environmentalist is quick to point out. The life-centricity of rampant
instrumental reasoning would be self-defeating if our attempts to control nature were
to result in our destruction, in which case the principle of active inference
as formulated by Friston would be precisely as incoherent as parasitic logic
(when the parasite kills itself by killing its host).
By contrast, the rival type of cognition takes for granted
all creatures’ frailties, the barbarity of natural selection, the grotesqueness
of what we call human progress, and the farcicality of our myriad self-deceits.
What’s optimal, then, from that meta-viewpoint may only indirectly be the
continuation of normal life and our automated pastimes. What’s paramount, though, would be the ecstasy of existential
cognition, the courage and sadness involved in attempting to see the world as
it is, which means as it would be without us. Just as the herd uses active
inference to control the unobserved causes of its sensory states, by way of
predicting or producing order and eliminating surprise (along with eliminating the higher-order
ecstasy of dread/angst/awe/deranged mirth), the intellectual super-elites, that
is, the omega men and women whose kingdom is God’s rather than Caesar’s,
to express the point mythically, use the
herd of normies, in turn. The herd’s
success in fitting into its natural or artificial environment is fodder for comedy
perceived only by the alienated watchers who
gravitate not to any statistical matching of regularities, but to the opposite,
to the abyss between life and lifelessness, to horror and “madness” rather than
happiness and compliance.
Instrumental reason entails, then, a hierarchy rather than a
duality. The divergence isn’t just between active and sensory states, life and
death, roughly speaking. Living things branch off, in turn, between those who
side blindly with life against death, without seeing the big picture, and those
who stand nowhere, estranged from both nature and our artificial oases. The
latter outsiders are torn, for example, between sympathizing with the
masses, who suffer because the world’s course isn’t directed to our benefit,
and being disgusted by our pretenses. Which is more contemptible, mindless
nature which can’t help itself even as it creates trillions of living creatures
only to ruin them, or those very creatures whose struggles are seldom heroic,
marred as they are by self-deception? Should we side with life or with death?
The mark of philosophical mastery seems to be the suffering from the doubt that
the answer to that question isn’t obvious.
None of which is to say that Friston’s theory is false, as
far as it goes. Exploitative reason is likely hardwired into all life by natural
selection. I’ve extrapolated from our preference for artificiality, or from
what you could think of as active inference, as the self-interested engagement with
the world that ends in the intelligent reengineering of nature, and have
speculated that the creation of artificial worlds represents a vindication of ancient animism. We fill nature with purpose and intention, creating the “spirits”
(which we now call functions) that we longed to see everywhere to feel finally at
home in what had been the haunted wilderness. The dubious leap is to suggest
that this instrumental perspective could provide for a theory of everything,
that there can be no counterexample or valid contrary way of life.
"The mark of philosophical mastery seems to be the suffering from the doubt that the answer to that question isn’t obvious. "
ReplyDeletebeautiful. as expected.
Thanks very much.
ReplyDelete