Savvy Western elites are suspicious of the modern
glorification of Reason. They’re aware that postmodernism began with a litany
of critiques of free thinking: David Hume maintained that we’re led by
emotions, not by reason; Herbert Spencer extended Darwin’s explanation of
biological design, reducing society to a set of animalistic compulsions that
should be allowed to play out without unnatural, governmental interference; Nietzsche
wrote that confidence in reason is a booster for resentful losers so they’ll
forget about their foiled will to power; Freud showed that there’s an
irrational unconscious mind that can only be recognized, not controlled by
rationality; Marx argued that ideologies are weapons in economic conflicts
between social classes. So much, then, for the early modern celebration of Reason!
We might have assumed, on the contrary, that the evident progress in the
eminently rational fields of science and technology should inspire us to admire
critical thinking, as we’ve lost lazy faith in feel-good dogmas. But it turns
out that reason ironically undermines itself, as in the above philosophical and
scientific discoveries as well as in Godel’s Incompleteness Theorem and the
quantum observer effect. Mathematical systems can’t consistently express every
true arithmetical statement, because such systems run up against the Liar’s
Paradox. And attempts to measure quantum phenomena perturb them so that a
neutral, objective view of them is impossible. (There’s also the intrinsic
uncertainty of measuring wavelike effects).
But there’s a deeper problem with reason—and here I’m
speaking about our general talent for thinking itself, not just the modern cult
of Reason. The problem isn’t that reason is a two-edged sword, that while
thinking has allowed us to prosper as a species, as we’ve learned how to
exploit natural processes, our power of understanding also saddens us with
knowledge of unpleasant facts such as death’s inevitability for all living
things or the universe’s undeadness. Reason is both a blessing and a
curse, but even this isn’t the problem with which I’m here concerned.
The deeper problem is difficult to articulate, since seeing it requires a rather
mystical, outsider’s view of human life; moreover,
there’s the looming paradox that if you express the problem reasonably, you may
have only reestablished rather than shed light on it. In a word, reason isn’t just cursed, figuratively speaking; it’s literally
a trap.
Reasoning and our Illusory Godhood
The trap becomes apparent when we compare our chief skill
with that of other species. Fish have fins that allow them to swim; birds’
wings enable them to fly; tigers run on four powerful legs in their hunt for
food; spiders spin webs to catch prey, and so on and so forth. These
animalistic virtues are plainly phenotypic, in that the animals have an advantage
that manifests as an outer, bodily attribute which equips them to flourish in a
specific environment. Our primary advantage is less tangible. True, we have
opposable thumbs and we walk on two legs, freeing up our arms to devise techniques
to compensate for our relatively weak bodies. But those mutations would be
useless without the modifications to our protohuman ancestors’ brain. That
which makes us human isn’t immediately visible to us in our daily life—unlike
an elephant’s trunk, a monkey’s prehensile tail, or a lizard’s scales, which
are apparent to them. Our brain gives rise to even more ethereal benefits,
namely language, autonomy, and culture, or in general the ability to think, to
understand virtually any situation and to take appropriate action. We
mythologize these aspects of personhood by calling them supernatural and
spiritual, telling all manner of bizarre religious stories to explain our
uniqueness in the animal world. In doing so, we mistake the inwardness and
complexity of our primary adaptation with crass transcendence. We don’t wear
our brain on our sleeve and the brain’s internal workings are astronomically
complicated; moreover, thinking isn’t a thing,
like a body part that plays some obvious role as a weapon in a competition for
resources. Thus, we’re tempted to think that we’re not really animals at all,
that we don’t belong in the material world of physical and biological machines.
As for thinking itself, its entrapment of the thinker is
insidious. With reason we merely organize the thoughts that incessantly occupy
our attention, stipulating to conceptual distinctions and appealing to rules of
reliable inferences. We follow trains of thought, testing ways of thinking and
of classifying phenomena, and in doing so we seem on the surface to be utterly
unlike the animals in their struggle for crude advantages. Animals merely fight
with their specialized body parts, whereas we see the world as it really is.
Animals are genetically driven to rely on their overt traits, but they aren’t
thereby misled to assume that the world revolves around their distinguishing robotic
characteristics. There’s obviously more to the world than flying, swimming, or
running, since nature throws up countless such innovations as life forms
attempt to take advantage of one or another opportunity in the struggle for a sustainable
way of life. But is there more to the
world than what can be thought about it? Does thinking exhaust the world’s
contents? Hamlet speculates that there’s a mismatch even in that respect
(“There are more things in heaven and earth, Horatio, than are dreamt of in
your philosophy”), but that's because he's just seen a ghost. The point is that while outward traits are obviously limited,
thinking feels as if it’s unlimited. Not only can we assign a name to every
phenomenon, including the zero to nothingness or an elliptical concept to that
which may elude our conceptual grasp, but we can imagine fictional worlds or
conceive of a multiverse of possible universes. We can plan for eventualities
in every earthly domain and can even
adapt ourselves to life in outer space. It’s
at least possible that for every fact there’s a corresponding thought, so that
the human specialization seems as large and impressive as the rest of the universe.
What Richard Rorty calls the mirror of nature, this protean ability of human understanding to
accommodate any real property, to respond to this or that situation with a
fitting representation, using language, logic, and mental symbols, is then readily
mistaken for supernatural transcendence.
After all, if we can mirror the whole world we must stand apart from everything
that’s thinkable, which lands us in an unknowable supernatural realm. Another
way of saying this is that objectivity is comparatively godlike; we seem able
to perceive reality rather than just to exercise a more pedestrian skill. That
is, we’re unlike the fish that tries to swim out of any trouble since that’s
all a fish can do—even when the fish is caught on a hook and parted from water.
We presume that when we think
realistically, we wield an infinite net to catch anything at all—not just prey
to fill our bellies, but any entity the world has to offer. We ignore our
subjective distractions and let the world speak for itself, as it
were, but only as a ploy to capture that part of the world in our conceptual
net, to add to our worldview so that it more and more adequately maps the terrain.
Objectivity seems like the fabled horn of plenty, the gift that keeps on giving. No
matter what we encounter, we can defend against it since we can absorb its image by
imagining fitting symbols in our understanding. Nothing escapes the power of
our mental map.
But we’re trapped by Reason if we contend that our power of
thinking transcends metaphors like those of nets or maps. Neither a net nor a
map stands entirely apart from what it captures. When we reason, we often presume
that we occupy our own world. We assume that we’re free from anything that lies
passive before our understanding, that when we come to terms with some
phenomenon we don’t interact with it, merely adding one more process to the
world, but we detach ourselves from what we contemplate so that we might have
ultimate power over it. Natural processes are limited and wholly undead
(mindlessly changing). For example, wind blowing through trees affects the
leaves by striking most of them on only one side, given the wind’s particular direction
and strength. Wind doesn’t get at the essence of leaves so that it can use them
under any circumstances. But the power of objective thinking seems much more
adaptable: we don’t merely project our biases such as our personality or
culture, but discover a leaf’s true identity and position, for example, right
down or up to the subatomic or cosmic levels. When we understand the real
world, we don’t interact with it as an animal might, by twisting and turning a
leaf hither and thither and using it in some predictable, blundering way;
instead, we seem to transcend the world, scrutinizing the leaf from all sides
in our imagination or in the laboratory, escaping to an inner or artificial microcosm
over which we’re sovereign. Far from
being merely subject to natural laws, like animals or the wind, the objective
mind assigns rules to its symbols so that we can ponder not just how the world
does work but how it ought to be changed.
Reason’s endless
capacity to capture the world in its net of symbols helps to generate the
illusion of our immateriality. We assume we must be made of some
supernatural substance, because this ability to be about anything at all, to be
consciously aware of anything and to fathom its hidden workings seems to remove
us from the world we reproduce in our mind. How can anything that’s merely part
of the world contain everything in that world, including an understanding of
itself? And yet this is just what we learn from biology, that cells each
contain the entire genetic code for building the whole organism. And nature is
superficially chaotic in its dynamic processes, since such processes converge
to those states that are mathematically represented by attractors, as
determined by fractal patterns within the apparent noise. Like the cells of an
organism, a fractal is self-referential in all of its parts, since however you
divide the whole or subdivide its parts, you’ll discover a copy of the whole
pattern. The brain is evidently like a
DNA code for the universe, in that it has the potential to represent the whole,
or it’s like a fractal pattern in which the history of the cosmos repeats
itself in symbolic form. At least, there’s no good reason to believe we’re
spiritual beings in any metaphysical sense.
After all, when we reason we aren’t perfectly removed from
the rest of the world. However the introverted genius may retreat to her room
and contemplate the universe’s mysteries, she can engage only in thought
processes as sustained by her brain. The brain is indeed walled off from the
rest of the body by the skull, and consciousness can be further removed by
means of a meditative state or even a sensory deprivation chamber, in which
case its thoughts and images may indeed unfold with little or no external
prompting, as in a psychedelic trip. But
the brain itself is a natural object—fiendishly complex, to be sure, but
part of nature nonetheless. Thinking of leaves, then, is like wind blowing
through the trees, in that each is a natural process that potentially brings
about some change in leaves. True, we can imagine things that don’t exist and
thus that can’t causally originate any such mental process. Moreover, unlike
institutional science, the ability to entertain fictions isn’t a byproduct of
more evolutionarily rooted skills. Contrary to empiricists, fictions don’t
arise as peculiar assemblages of puzzle-piece “sense data.” Indeed, just as
children begin by whimsically interpreting the world as a giant fiction, so too
our species was originally outfitted with a mythopoeic mindset so that bizarre
religions were central to the earliest cultures. Objective reason is an individual
and historical modification of the ability to freely play with symbols, not the
other way around.
In any case, the imagining of fictions is a natural process
comparable to quantum wave functions which carry the potential to bring about
alternative realities. Just as anything is potentially different, the higher
brain reflects that variability in its mental maps. We don’t confine ourselves
to mapping actual reality, but delight in speculating on magical links between
phenomena, which personalize nature and make it seem less monstrous, that is,
less zombie-like. This freedom to conceive of unpredictable, counterfactual worlds is as
natural as the fractal order within a chaotic system or as the wave-like (and
thus merely statistical, indeterminate) foundation of all material phenomena. Everything
we perceive is ghostly in that all things have the quantum chance to be
measured otherwise and might even actually unfold differently in other
universes. If anything, the brain is a
nexus in which the undead playfulness at the decaying heart of nature is
amplified. Thus, the mental representation of fictions isn’t so anomalous
that it warrants the positing of anything supernatural.
Now, Reason is no ordinary trap. We’re bound to be misled by
what our minds tend to do, and so the trap isn’t something you just may or may
not fall into. We can reflect on the social damages done by our self-entrapment
(on religious wars, egoistic selfishness, bigotries, etc), but as long as we’re being our brainy
selves we’ll feel like superpowerful lords of creation, because we’ll seem to
be divorced from what we objectively hold in the grip of our linguistic symbols.
Indeed, the subject-object dichotomy is likely the source of that sexual
perversion, the power play of sadists and masochists—which is actually most
revealing of the general horror of sexuality, the impersonal public praise of sex notwithstanding. We learn to be domineering or
submissive from our success at rationally mastering the natural world. That’s
why nature is typically personified as a female in religious myth, because men
are better suited to the social role of sadists (owing to their greater
physical strength and to their proclivity to think in terms of rigid positions in space
and of subordination to rules rather than in terms of mutually reinforcing
relationships). Our brains play out the flow of nature in symbolic form before
our inner eye and we feel like gods surveying the whole of reality, empowered also
to recreate the world since we come equipped to draft nature’s blueprint. But
again, however much reason empowers us, our separation from the known world is
an illusion. When we reason, we merely carry out one more natural process that’s
added to the list of those operative throughout the universe. To be sure, there
are levels of complexity and of relative transcendence within nature, but not an
absolute kind that propels us to literal godhood.
Truth and Power
What, then, is the process of objectively knowing something?
Isn’t there a crucial difference between getting the facts wrong or right? What
is truth if not some mirroring of a
phenomenon by a set of symbols? For example, the ancients had hardly any idea
what the stars in the sky actually are, whereas now we surely have abundant
information and can say with much rational justification that stars are
thermonuclear fusion reactors that evolve and differ depending on their mass
and so forth. Does this mean stars aren’t gods, as the ancients thought? Well,
if gods are the sources of life, then stars are indeed divine. But are they literally gods or just metaphorically
so? And yet how meaningful would that distinction have been to the ancients? Perhaps
the ancients’ beliefs can’t fairly be judged according to modern criteria because
the cultures that define the meaning of our symbols are largely incommensurable.
So were ancient and modern people to debate the nature of stars, they might
well just talk past each other—until one side would go native and adopt the
foreign way of thinking.
Does this mean there’s no such thing as truth? Don’t we know
much more about stars than the ancients? Well, knowledge depends on interests,
since we don’t expend sufficient effort to learn about that which doesn’t
interest us. Modernists are interested in understanding natural mechanisms and
we’ve inherited and devised many techniques to accumulate that kind of
knowledge. So we know a lot about how stars work. For the most part, the
ancients were interested more in teleological questions because they lacked the
techniques to apply much mechanistic knowledge. They wanted to know the purpose
of sunshine and so they conceived of the world in mythical, quasi-personal terms. Do we
know for certain that the world is fundamentally impersonal? Has science
demonstrated atheism? Only if we assume certain epistemic criteria that slant
that philosophical question in
atheism’s favour. You see, the ultimate philosophical questions aren’t matters
of empirical or rational knowledge. The answers are largely speculative and
thus lie more in the domains of ethics, aesthetics, and religion. Truth in
their cases, in the sense of surface factuality, is beside the point. And as
for empirical truth, that’s mainly a matter of instrumental power over what’s explained. To say that we know more
about the universe than the ancients isn’t to say that our symbols magically
agree with the world whereas the ancients’ symbols were duds, but that we have
superior control over nature. And that control is one natural
process that unites the rational subject and the known object: the subject uses
tools to alter the object, and so reason is a step in that development. We
gather information, our brains churn with interpretations and goals, and out
pop opportunities for rearranging the landscape.
Mystics criticize Reason by saying that ironically the deepest
answers sought by logical, evidence-based thinkers are obtained in a
pre-rational way. As soon as we start to reason, we fall from grace, as it
were; that is, we fall into the trap and succumb to the egoistic illusion that
bars us from a deeper, philosophical understanding. To take some pop cultural
examples, in the Tron movie remake the Jeff Bridges character paradoxically
equates doing nothing with a superior kind of productivity. Instead of scheming
with an overactive mind, we should let the world unfold around us and become
one with it, as a Daoist would say. In the film called Cube, a group is
imprisoned in a giant, subsectioned cube whose sections shift places and kill
the prisoners off one by one. But it turns out that instead of fleeing from the
room they first occupy, to try to solve the mystery of their giant prison, they
should have stayed put in the room in which they first awake since that’s the
room that would have brought them to the exit. Such movies play on the mystical
principle, then, that Reason is part of the fallen world, ironically bringing
us to a dead end. Far from allowing us to see reality, reason perpetuates
certain illusions such as that of the independence of all things from each
other. Now, contrary to mysticism, there is no absolute pre-rational knowledge
such as mystical access to God or Source energy. Prior to reason, historically
and epistemically speaking, there’s just the childlike artistic imagination and
the will to take an existential leap of faith. Again, truth in the sense of a
mirroring relation is irrelevant as well as an illusion brought on by the trap
of objectivity, that is, by the feeling that we stand alone in our act of
understanding something, occupying a view from nowhere.
Willful Withdrawal from Natural Life
Ascetic detachment is ultimately just more natural creativity,
although in this case what’s created is transitory anti-nature. If mentality has
a fractal structure that recapitulates the variety of forms in nature, as we
echo what we perceive in our thoughts and languages and cultural images, there’s
some courage or stubbornness in occupying a higher, mystical state in which we recognize
that dreary dynamic and choose instead to become dead ends, to decline to participate in nature’s decay.
However, that choice is tragic, at best, because the world’s decay, which is to
say its impersonal flow to nowhere, is unstoppable. The evolution of nature is a tidal wave of black zombie ichor that
mutates for no reason of its own, although some of its mutations evolve a taste for Reason and the mental space for an incessant encore of nature’s symphony of
moans, coughs, and screeches. Perhaps asceticism is yet more fractal
repetition—only the existential naysayer harkens back to the ultimate personal negation,
to some insane and corrupt God’s act of universal creation through
self-destruction, as Philipp Mainlander speculated.
In any case, given the tragic limitations of these forms of
transcendence, of objective thinking and aesthetic refinement which shocks the
likes of introverts and artists with a vision of the world’s monstrousness, salvation
may come in mind-numbing nostalgia for children’s mythopoeic playfulness. If
only we could remain in the wonderland of our imagination and not grow into
rational dominators who are corrupted by the illusion of our power over the
world! If only the quantum foam of possibilities didn’t collapse into actual law-bound
worlds; if only happy-go-lucky toddlers didn’t fall into the state of either adult
egoism or the existential rebel’s self-righteousness. But those falls happen
because Being lurches onward, being essentially and appallingly undead. Like
black comedy, the opiate of nostalgia saves the enlightened few only by allowing
them moments in which they can forget the existential plight of all sentient
beings that learn they’re part of the colossal abomination that is the natural
universe.
Wow, Benjamin. This is a PARTICULARLY bleak piece! Not even the (feeble) hope of salvation through nihilism here!
ReplyDeleteI would say bravo, but I'm not sure that would help any!
Yeah, this article's a reminder of why I speak only of tragic heroism for naturalists and atheists. In the end, we all receive bad news as sentient creatures. While we're here, we can either suffer relentlessly in nihilistic anticipation of our dismal fate, demean ourselves by retreating to exoteric delusions, or make the best of the existential situation with esoteric wisdom, including pantheistic religion, aesthetic sensibility, and dark comedy.
DeleteGood to see you back, Ben. I've been needing a bit of cosmic perspective of late, despite the depressing short story I just completed.
ReplyDeleteThanks! Just to clarify, as I did in an earlier post, I'm not putting an end to this blog, but because of my new job I have less time to write. Still, I have lots more to say! The next one will be on myths about competition.
DeleteI assume therefore that given the above you now wholeheartedly support antinatalism. I fail to see how you cannot.
ReplyDeleteMy view has always been that the best we can do is to be tragic heroes. This article supports the tragic part. So my view hasn't changed. And I still don't think it implies antinatalism, as I explain in my YouTube debate with Inmendham and in my article on AN.
DeleteThe key question is whether the good of tragic heroism is outweighed by the harm done by the tragedy of natural life. In a nutshell, which is more significant, the tragedy or the heroism? The antinatalist needs an argument showing that the ethical and aesthetic values of our heroic virtues--the emergent, transcendent properties of creativity, black comedy, etc, as I put it in my YouTube debate--count for nothing compared to the suffering that happens because natural life is tragic (we're part of an undead god decaying to nowhere, etc).
That argument typically takes a utilitarian form, but I find that sort of reasoning crass and unpersuasive. Let's not confuse speculative philosophy with mathematics, as though we were dealing here with quantities that can be measured, as opposed to qualities that must be evaluated by aesthetic taste and ultimately by an existential leap of faith.
Let's leave aside the utilitarian take. Can you provide one good solid reason for procreation knowing what we do about existence? And what is the point in producing 'tragic heroes'? The world doesn't need them, or anyone else, and simply because one is aware of life's futility doesn't make one 'heroic'.
DeleteNor is this tragic heroism, assuming it exists, much use to those being blown to bits/dying of cancer/suffering from daily abuse etc etc. Suffering is only a spectacle to evaluated aesthetically when you're not the one suffering. Be careful not to fall into the 'aesthetics as anaesthetics' trap.
But thank you for the post. I thoroughly enjoyed it.
'suffering is only a spectacle to be evaluated aesthetically when you're not the one suffering'
ReplyDeleteAnd in fact the notion of evaluating suffering in an aesthetic manner is revolting and runs the risk of falling into the worst kind of Nietzschean hyperbole.
A solid reason for procreating (i.e. continuing our species), knowing that natural life is horrific and absurd? Nature is much more interesting with life in it than without. No one would be around to appreciate that fact if there were no life, but that’s irrelevant. Likewise, even if everyone were happy about their life because of their delusions, the fact would remain that their life is absurd. But even absurd life is more interesting than no life. What’s most interesting about life is that it provides the opportunity for a kind of payback through existential rebellion against monstrous nature (i.e. for degrees of ascetic withdrawal and renunciation). Again, undead nature can’t appreciate the irony when sentient creatures use their talents to thwart the genes and create transcendent, unnatural habitats in which we can play god, but once more, epistemology isn’t metaphysics. Whether anyone knows about some fact or has reason to believe it’s true doesn’t affect the truth value, assuming the fact in question is objective.
DeleteNote that I’m not saying everyone should procreate. As I’ve explained elsewhere, those with the darkest worldview might not make for fitting parents. But they might still cheer on others to procreate, to continue our species, if only for the comedic value our exploits provide those who’ve been initiated into the esoteric circles of wisdom--not to mention the value of existential rebellion.
I agree that just knowing that nature is monstrous doesn’t make you a hero. The heroism comes from the acts of rebellion, from the critical thinking which acts as a screen against irresponsible myths and delusions, from renouncing cheap opportunities for happiness, and so on.
Can those who suffer a lot afford to be heroic in this ascetic fashion? Perhaps not, depending on their afflictions. So others can be tragic heroes on their behalf. Indeed, Buddhists and other ascetics withdraw from the charade of natural life largely because they’re horrified by their knowledge that *everyone* suffers.
My values are aesthetic and ethical. What I do is reconstruct morality in aesthetic terms. So if suffering is bad, I think of this badness not as a case of violating anything like a divine commandment (since there’s no God) or as a case merely of physical pain (since contrary to utilitarians like Inmendham, the fact of physical pain isn’t self-evidently bad). No, suffering is bad because it’s disgusting and grotesque. As I explain in “Life is Art” and “Morality, Living Art, and the Undead Muse,” all things can be interpreted as artworks in so far as they’re creations that are subject to aesthetic reactions. Natural forces create; therefore, nature is full of art.
I understand your point that an aesthetic evaluation of suffering is revolting if this means a trivialization of that suffering. You want to say that suffering is objectively bad, not just bad as a matter of arbitrary taste. But the way I think of aesthetics, aesthetic value comes out as objective; indeed, I compare the aesthetic attitude with scientific detachment and objectivity. (See “Life is Art.”)
Anyway, thanks very much for your incisive comments. And thanks for reading!
http://rantswithintheundeadgod.blogspot.ca/2013/11/life-as-art-morality-and-natures.html
http://rantswithintheundeadgod.blogspot.ca/2014/02/morality-living-art-and-undead-muse.html
What if the world were to end in a couple of decades? Would it make sense to procreate?
ReplyDeleteWhat kind of existential heroism could be displayed in that case?
I found an online community that believes we're heading to extinction in the near future based on scientific data. You might want to check Nature Bats Last.
Could this be a scientific basis for nihilism?
This is actually the first example I gave on RWUG of existential heroism, the end of humanity as depicted by Olaf Stapledon in First and Last Men. See my article, Inkling of an Unembarassing Postmodern Religion.
DeleteNo, in that situation, assuming we were certain of our doom and had no way of preserving our species or of rescuing certain members, like in Superman, procreation wouldn't make sense.
But what exactly do you mean by "nihilism"? Do you mean an absence of values or libertinism/Sadism/Satanism, that is, the freedom to take up any value or goal, such as murder, rape, etc, given that all values are arbitrary? Would you advocate suicide/living in a cave were the world ending soon? Or megalomaniacal evil and anarchy? Nihilism seems consistent with either of these options.
Anyway, I think the RWUG philosophy would apply even to this most dire situation. After all, we all individually die after only several decades, so adding the possibility of mass collective death doesn't fundamentally change the existential predicament. Death is mainly what makes life absurd, tragic, and horrific. How we learn to deal with that fact determines our character, our moral worth, and whether we're human (nearly enlightened), transhuman (alpha god/oligarch or omega/enlightened ascetic), or subhuman (deluded and enslaved beta).
I'll check out the website. I note that it says right away that readers should reconsider if they're contemplating suicide.
If the world ends , the most heroic thing to do in my opinion is just to sit back and watch it happen. Be proud you were lucky enough to see that part and maybe have a party celebrating the absurdity of existence. Definitely more heroic than suicide or fanatic and desperate prayers to a non existent god. Unless it's the rapture...
DeleteSounds like good advice to me, Logan. Indeed, suicide wouldn't be so heroic, although a show like The Walking Dead raises the question of whether still having faith in our species even after the catastrophe of the zombie apocalypse wouldn't be as absurd as monotheistic religious faith currently is. There's a character in that show who I think eventually chooses to kill herself but who first looks with pity in her eyes at her sister who would rather go on struggling despite the horrific risk of being eaten alive by zombies.
DeleteThere may indeed be extreme cases in which life is unbearably absurd and suicide is the only responsible choice. More precisely, it's not then a choice between life or suicide, but between two ways of dying, one by being eaten by zombies, say, and another, more peaceful and self-controlled way. Or look at those who jumped out of the Twin Towers on 911. Their choice was between that terrifying fate and burning to death. We're going to die either way.
Anyway, I am generally against suicide. My point is that suicide may not be absolutely wrong under every conceivable circumstance (such as the end of the world).